[RRE]Institutions and the Entrepreneurial Self

From: Phil Agre (pagreat_private)
Date: Wed Dec 19 2001 - 17:09:07 PST

  • Next message: Phil Agre: "[RRE]pointers"

    =-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=
    This message was forwarded through the Red Rock Eater News Service (RRE).
    You are welcome to send the message along to others but please do not use
    the "redirect" option.  For information about RRE, including instructions
    for (un)subscribing, see http://dlis.gseis.ucla.edu/people/pagre/rre.html
    =-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=
    
    
    
      Institutions and the Entrepreneurial Self
    
      Phil Agre
      http://dlis.gseis.ucla.edu/pagre/
    
      Version of 19 December 2001.
      9000 words.
    
    
    Although reviews of my column about how-to's were generally kind,
    sociologists demurred from some of my generalizations about their
    field's treatment of the relationship between the institution
    and the self.  The issue, you might recall, is the extent to which
    institutions define us.  Everybody occupies locations in several
    institutions: professional, political, medical, educational, family,
    religious, and so on.  And every one of those institutions offers
    us a personality: language, beliefs, habits, artefacts, interactional
    style, and so on.  The question is, do institutions completely
    remake us in their image, or do we remain to some degree ourselves?
    It is not an easy question, since it could mean several things.
    Even if we know what the question means, it is not entirely clear
    how we could know the answer.  For example, we can study doctors and
    conclude that they walk and talk exactly the way that the institution
    of medicine wants them to, but that proves nothing until we determine
    whether they had already believed in the institution and consciously
    chose to acquire its ways.  We would also have to confront the
    fact that we are all shaped by numerous institutions: since no one
    institution defines who we are, do we thereby transcend them all?
    These are important questions for us now because of the tremendous
    power of information technology to facilitate institutional change.
    As institutions change, people change too.  We need to know how we're
    changing and what choice we have.
    
    I want to respond to the demurrals of the sociologists, but to address
    the question properly we need to know where it came from.  Because
    the question depends on the particulars of each case, we would need
    to consider the case in each continent or broad cultural area on
    its own terms.  So I want to talk about Europe and the United States,
    since it is mainly European and American ideas that are inscribed
    in information technology today.  I want to sketch in fast-forward the
    history of the relationship between institutions and the human person,
    as well as the social context in which certain ideas about the subject
    emerged.  A thorough version of this story would require a long book,
    but I only want to develop enough raw material to provoke inquiry into
    our own situation today.
    
    European thought about the distant past is naturally rooted in
    European myths.  One such myth is that ancient Europe was a simple,
    homogenous, primitive place.  In some senses of course it was, but the
    intuition is still misleading.  When communication and transportation
    technologies are poorly developed, institutions develop more or less
    independently in each locality.  Of course, the institutions in a
    given region must contend with the climate and natural resources,
    and with the practicalities of growing food and keeping people alive.
    Even so, it is an important intuition that the natural condition
    of human society is one of institutional diversity.  Institutions
    are well-understood as routinized accommodations among competing
    interests -- people's everyday interactions, in which conflict and
    compromise are omnipresent, settle into routines which then take on
    a life of their own.  These routines take different forms in different
    places, if only because there are many paths that the settling-down
    of routines could possibly take.  So institutional diversity needs
    no explanation; what needs explaining is the establishment of uniform
    institutions across a wide area.
    
    That is why the Roman Empire played such a central role in setting
    European institutions on their path.  Rome managed to establish a
    relatively uniform institutional system across large parts of Europe.
    People throughout the Empire came to understand themselves as the
    objects of administrative representations and procedures, and they
    were eventually exposed to the idea of a universal religion and a
    hierarchical Church.  This is not to say that Rome succeeded in
    homogenizing the entire population; invaders' institutions enter into
    complex syntheses with the institutions that they encounter.  Even
    so, the Romans (more so than, say, the Ottomans) worked to homogenize
    (for example) the political workings of cities, with the result that
    some areas of Europe ended up with more homogenous institutions -- and
    thus with different ideas about people and their place in society --
    than others.
    
    When Rome fell, a natural experiment took place.  How do institutions
    develop in homogenous areas versus heterogeneous areas?  The answer
    is not simple.  The space of possibilities can be understood simply
    in terms of the relationships among three levels of society: the towns,
    the regions, and the nation as a whole.  In England, regional powers
    established themselves as coequal with the monarchy, partly by drawing
    on account of the institutional similarities among them.  In France,
    the monarchy crushed the regional powers, consolidating its control
    by developing local homogeneity ever further.  Spain was able to
    consolidate central control, but it never suppressed political
    turmoil between the regions and the center sufficiently to establish
    a functional administrative system.  And Italy failed to consolidate
    central control at all; instead, Roman ideas and institutional forms
    developed in various directions in each locality.  Again, institutions
    can follow many paths from the same starting-point.  Outside the
    Empire, things were just as diverse.  Sweden consolidated central
    control largely because the monarchy could ally with the towns
    against the depredations of regional nobles.  Germany, on the other
    hand, retained its local institutional diversity at a very high level
    well into the nineteenth century.  In each case, the opinions toward
    government in each country are explained to a surprising degree by
    the patterns that took form a thousand years ago.  So too the opinions
    about culture.  The concept of distinct national cultures arose first
    in Italy, where it failed to compete with inherited Roman ideas, and
    it then flourished in Germany, where it provided the ideological basis
    for a nationalist campaign of political and institutional unification.
    
    Even so, this story of independent development is far from complete.
    When the European economy began to revive in the 11th century, the
    need for institutions of all types was severe.  And the main source
    of these institutions was the one institution that had maintained
    a sophisticated intellectual foundation throughout, the Church.
    The 11th and 12th centuries saw a revolution in Western institutions,
    including the universities and the modern legal system.  The legal
    system was based the secularization on canon law, so that for example
    the idea of punishment for a crime derived from the codified schedules
    of penance that the medieval church had drawn up in its attempt to
    administer the spiritual lives of a far-flung population in a uniform
    way.  This pattern is common on two levels: existing institutions
    often serve as analogues for the invention of new institutions, and
    modern secular ideas routinely develop from older religious ideas.
    
    So even though textbooks have tended to focus on the political
    divergences that I described above, the quieter development of the
    institutional foundations of Western society was more or less unified.
    This too represents a pattern: people involved in intellectual work
    (meaning administration as well as scholarship) are interested in
    talking to their opposite numbers in other organizations, regardless
    of boundaries, simply because no individual is intellectually capable
    of performing such work on their own.  Scholarship and administration
    require the communication and transportation infrastructures that
    earlier societies lacked.  (The problem is roads, inns, and safety,
    not horses and vehicles -- it's not that hard to walk from one end
    of Europe to the other.)  They also require social networks, which
    scholars build easily, and a lingua franca, Latin.  But there is
    a complex tale to be told about the maintenance of these logistical
    foundations of European collective cognition during the medieval era,
    as well as their growing complexity later on.
    
    What is more, the religious origins of the institutional machinery
    of the West influenced broader Western conceptions of the person.
    Administrative bureaucracies assumed an authority that they modeled
    on that of the Church, with administrators serving as mediators of
    a universal and permanent law.  Western concepts of equality and
    the rule of law have their origin here, as do Western concepts of
    paternalism and social reform.  Social control emerges not as the
    arbitrary subjection of individuals to one another, but as impersonal,
    rational procedures: a shift, as Weber might say, from substantive to
    procedural rationality.
    
    The modern state, however, arose not from the independent political
    development of different countries, nor from the uniform development
    of the bureacracies that ran them, but from the era of Darwinian
    warfare that followed.  The absolutist era in Europe is often told as
    the history of conquests, alliances, and territories, but on a deeper
    level it is the story of war as the motive force for the competitive
    development of institutions.  Consider the most basic requirement of
    war: taxes.  Warring states confront two facts: wars are expensive,
    and people do not want to pay their taxes.  And so victory in war
    went largely to the state that developed the most sophisticated
    means of extracting taxes from the populace.  One can extract taxes
    through arbitrary theft, but that system is inefficient and leads
    to revolts.  The key to tax-collection is record-keeping, and the
    states that succeeded in war did so by developing rational methods for
    keeping track of the populace.  This was not easy.  Many people had
    the same name, traditional farming practices were complicated, and the
    diversity of local institutional arrangements frustrated centralized
    rule-making.  Whatever forces for homogenization already existed, the
    constant pressure to collect taxes increased them.  This is the era
    when people were assigned acquire surnames and farmers were assigned
    their own plots of land rather than farming different plots in
    different seasons according to local customs.  It is the era of
    representations such as censuses and maps, and the era when states
    rearranged people's lives to fit the representations.
    
    There is another complex tale to be told about the interaction between
    this Europe-wide development of modern administrative procedures and
    the diversity of political institutions with which they interacted.
    Each set of institutions had its own ideas about people and their
    lives, including ideas about power and authority, honor and valor,
    mind and body, health and disease, wealth and poverty, the spiritual
    and the corporeal, and so on.  The ideas often conflicted: indeed,
    the conflict between administrative neutrality and the divine right
    of kings was the driving force for a vast outpouring of intellectual
    creativity.  Yet the ideas themselves developed in specific contexts.
    In England, ideas could be spun by independent nobles and their
    intellectual clients.  English intellectual tracts were often written
    as moves in savage political conflicts, and it is never certain
    whether our modern-day interpretations of them as abstract philosophy
    correspond to the way they were read at the time.  Their struggles
    for autonomy relative to the monarch and authority relative to the
    lower orders helps explain the peculiar combination of liberalism and
    hierarchy that later coalesced into modern conservatism.  In France,
    on the other hand, the production of ideas was regulated in the same
    way as everything else, in a minutely stratified social system.  Court
    life in absolutist France was a war zone of social competition whose
    potential for violence was largely domesticated sublimated beneath
    norms of polite emptiness.  Polite conversation was all, and scholars
    could only pursue their serious social inquiries on the fringes of the
    system or beneath the guise of pleasant cultivation.  Things haven't
    changed much since.
    
    In talking about the relation between institutions and the self,
    therefore, we are talking at two levels: the ways that institutions
    shaped everyone in the society (or tried to), and the ways that
    institutions shaped the people who developed the ideas within them
    (and thus, to some extent, the ideas themselves).  Institutions are
    routinized interactions among people, but they are also ideas put
    into practice.  Institutions formalize and structure relationships
    between people, and they do so by inducing everyone to insert
    themselves into a certain order.  Now, many scholars have understood
    this process in terms of "power" and "resistance", as if institutions
    were always foreign impositions.  But enough history has been
    recounted here to make clear that things are more complicated.
    By focusing on the case of taxes, you can indeed make the case that
    institutions exist to impose something artificial on the natural order
    that went before.  By focusing on the case of religion, however, you
    can make a very different case.  The fact is, the Church can operate
    with such a flat hierarchy because the common people want religion.
    Organized churches in many societies go through cycles of decadence
    and regeneration as people demand that religious authorities act
    religious.  This is another model of institutions: people subscribe to
    them because they embody what people believe and deliver what people
    want.  So which theory is correct?  They both are, to varying degrees,
    and the hard problem is to understand the relationship between the
    models in different contexts.  And the problem is reflexive, since
    institutions both produce ideas and embody ideas.  We inherit both
    the institutions and the ideas, and we only understand ourselves
    as institutional beings as we understand both kinds of inheritance.
    
    Institutions, as I've observed, tend to take on a life of their own.
    And so it is that the institutions that arose in the absolutist era
    in Europe survived the passing of monarchy.  Institutions are embodied
    in diverse ways: not simply in written rules but also in language,
    habits, values, knowledge, strategies, and artefacts, all of it
    interlocking into a way of life that easily reproduces itself from
    one generation to the next.  In that sense institutional origin
    stories are always misleading, since everyone inherits an institutional
    system, and thus a collection of social roles and much else, just
    by joining into the way of life that they find already in progress
    around them.  Even so, institutions are not machines.  They are living
    things that give shape to the ambitions of the individuals and groups
    within them.  It is a mistake to think of institutions as pacifying
    people.  Institutions do not brainwash people or turn them into sheep.
    Indeed, their greatest role is providing the ground rules for people's
    conflicts and the resources for people's strategies.  If institutions
    were wholly alien impositions then we could not understand why people
    sign up with them.  On the other hand, it is not as though people's
    goals exist fully formed prior to their signing up with institutions.
    People's goals draw on the forms of imagination that are available in
    a culture, and they generally belong to the restricted range of goals
    that a person in a given place and time could realistically expect to
    achieve.  It follows that the supposed philosophical problem of free
    will is not much of a challenge to a theory of institutions.
    
    Consider, then, the conditions in which sociology first took form.
    It happened in France.  The beheading of the monarch did not behead
    the institutions that the ancien regime had created; in fact, the
    Revolutionary universalism helped consolidate bureaucratic control.
    In a society of absolutism, feudal arbitrariness, and clerical
    corruption, bureaucratic rationality was an attractive alternative.
    It makes perfect sense, then, that the Revolution would institute a
    theocracy of reason, and that a regime beset by foreign enemies and
    domestic reaction would place such a priority on establishing the
    metric system.  Although the Revolution eventually failed politically
    and militarily, it won intellectually, as none of its competitors
    established anything like a competing intellectual or social vision.
    
    It is thus that sociology emerged in the 19th century as a science
    of society in the form of a religion of reason.  The literal idea
    of a religion of reason, complete with a liturgy and symbolism, was
    generally regarded as an embarrassment, and the people who invented
    modern sociology fell into disrepute because they actually believed
    what they were saying.  Yet the fact remains, contradictory as it
    seems, that sociology began life as a secularized form of reason:
    social engineering for a deified state.  Individual human beings
    have no special place in this picture of society; they are simply
    the atoms of social physics and the bricks of social architecture.
    But the institutional arrangements that once collected taxes in
    a rational manner had now made society visible from its center,
    and the imagination of the time took for granted a transparency
    of social processes that had not been imaginable centuries before.
    This kind of transparency has often been interpreted as a license
    for totalitarianism, and in some contexts it has been used that way.
    But it is important to see that the secularized religion of reason
    is not very specific about the institutional forms in which it should
    be embodied.  It has served just as well for corporations as for
    communism, and in practice it serves to organize an archipelago of
    institutional agendas whose family relations require a more complex
    analysis.
    
    The actual field of sociology was founded slightly later by Durkheim.
    He was not so crudely scientistic as his predecessors; his main
    concern was to establish not a secularized religion but an autonomous
    intellectual discipline within the expanding and secularizing
    institution of the university.  Autonomy was the key for Durkheim.
    He wanted above all for "society" to be a self-contained intellectual
    category, sealed off both from the categories of neighboring fields
    (psychology, for example, then also taking form) and from outside
    the academic world (i.e., the Church).  Durkheim wanted to define
    a space of social facts that could not be reduced to other kinds
    of facts, collective representations that could not be reduced to
    individual cognition, and so on.  Durkheim's concern for autonomy
    is understandable in the context of social theory's origins in the
    ancien regime, when the all-encompassing court culture made serious
    intellectual work impossible simply by making serious public talk
    of any sort impossible.  This pattern too is widespread: institutions
    exist to organize and mediate social ambitions, and so the dynamics of
    institutional life consist largely of the segmentary politics by which
    different groups try to carve out zones of autonomy for themselves.
    Of course, autonomy means different things in different cultures,
    and people in social democracies will probably deny even caring about
    it.  Autonomy can mean raising your crops without having to serve
    in the military, or it can mean doing your research without having to
    shape either the form or the content of your thought to the pressure
    of other agendas.  Then the very strategies by which individuals and
    groups fight for their autonomy become institutionalized themselves,
    passed along by diverse routes to others whose circumstances and goals
    may well have changed.
    
    Meanwhile, the United States was founded in a rebellion against
    an insane king.  Different segments of the country understood this
    rebellion in different ways, from the rationalism and republicanism
    of the men who wrote the Constitution to the communitarianism and
    conspiracy theories of the religious dissidents.  Europeans understood
    America through the screen of their own utopian traditions, and
    Americans understood themselves to be living out a contradictory
    mixture of millennial promises that were expressed in egalitarianism,
    commerce,e and religious revival.  Having been modeled on ideas that
    the immigrants imported and transformed, American institutions and
    intellectual life then developed more or less independently of Europe.
    We take for granted today that intellectual influences flow easily
    between continents, but that situation dates only to the era of cheap
    air travel in the 1970s; before then, the reception of foreign ideas
    was slow and fallible.
    
    This is the context in which we can understand the emergence of
    sociological ideas in the United States.  Although American scholars
    had written about social issues in religious and political contexts,
    professionalized sociology became established only with Talcott
    Parsons at Harvard in the middle of the 20th century.  Parsons'
    influence on American social thought is well documented; what is less
    documented is his influence on American life in general.  Parsons had
    two things going for him.  First, he was an intellectual arbitrageur.
    He was the scholar who imported European sociology into the United
    States, most importantly in "The Structure of Social Action", which
    he presented as a study of Durkheim, Weber, Pareto, and Marshall.
    In fact, "The Structure of Social Action" was primarily a study
    of Parsons, who projected his own views of society onto the European
    scholars whose worked he claimed to describe.  This is a common
    problem with the reception of new ideas; people understand new things
    through the prism of what they know, and the distortions introduced by
    that prism are often severe.
    
    But Parsons was not just running an import business.  He had the great
    fortune to establish an American school of sociology in the era of
    social reform in the mid-20th century.  The New Deal was founded on
    an intellectual base of the Social Gospel, Progressive good government,
    and antitrust, but the social welfare programs of the 1960s were built
    on sociology.  The demand for social science grew enormously, and so
    did the universities where social research was conducted and taught.
    A whole generation that took tenured jobs during that period is about
    to retire, and we will see their influence most clearly in retrospect
    as they do.  What Parsons provided was not simply a canon for the
    study of sociology but a formula for sociological work on any subject.
    Parsons' theory, in accord with the American variety of conservative
    social thought that had grown up in that era, was called functionalism.
    Its central idea is that society is fitted together in a coherent and
    stable fashion, and that each element of society can be analyzed in
    terms of the role it plays in the functioning of the whole.  Parsonian
    sociology is remarkable for its sheer volume and for the local rigor
    of its argument; it is hardly trivial.  It has been a productive
    object of dispute, and has also provided a supply of raw material for
    other research programs since.  High-quality neofunctionalist research
    is done to the present day.
    
    The main complaint against Parsons was his "oversocialized" view of
    the human person.  Because he viewed society as a stable structure
    into which everything fits comfortably, it was hard to imagine how
    anything could change.  For Parsons, the individual was socialized
    into institutions by internalizing their values.  This concern with
    socialization was hardly new with Parsons, who inherited it from
    the longstanding concern with the incorporation of immigrants into
    American society and especially American industry.  That background
    may help explain the tendency of sociologists in that era to regard
    an individual's existing values as leftovers, even implicitly as a
    danger to social order.  It may also help explain the nature of the
    reaction to Parsons and the ideological tendency that he represented:
    the celebration of dissent from a suffocating conformity.
    
    Throughout this story, ideas have tended to oscillate between two
    extremes: on one extreme, you have theories in which individuals exist
    prior to the invasion of alien institutions, and on another extreme,
    you have theories in which institutions entirely enclose individuals,
    structuring their lives inside and out.  The individuals may be
    understood as good or bad, and the institutions too.  As so often, the
    opposite extremes are united underneath, joined in their apprehension
    of a dichotomy between the autonomous agent and the socialized self.
    This dichotomy is the starting-point of most Western thought about
    institutions, and no theory of institutions should be taken seriously
    unless it analyzes the dichotomy and seeks middle ground.  The facts
    are straightforward: people are partially defined by institutions and
    partially independent of them; they partially embrace the values that
    insitutions offer while partially maintaining a critical distance from
    those values; they partially embody the new ways of life that emerging
    institutions create while also partially embodying the older ways of
    life that predated them; they partially cooperate with the forms of
    rationality that the institution organizes while partially subverting
    those forms of rationality as well.  Just saying all this, of course,
    does not solve the problem.  It hardly *defines* the problem.  But
    at least it provides a standard with which to eliminate from serious
    consideration those theories that collapse into one triviality or the
    other.
    
    Thus my complaints against Foucault.  Conservatives and cynics
    argue that left-wing academics shifted their allegiance from Marx
    to Foucault when communism fell, and the timing is not far off.
    Foucault hardly replaces Marx, though, since he provides nothing like
    a political economy.  Foucault's central question is the constitution
    of the self: the categories and distinctions that are inscribed in
    people's lives through ideologies, practices, disciplines, artefacts,
    language -- through institutions.  If you believe that social
    ills derive from the artificial categories that society imposes on
    people, then the path to liberation seems to lie through a disruption
    of categories and a subversion of institutions.  This view does not
    come from nowhere: conservatism in many countries, and certainly
    in France, Germany, and the American South, has long meant precisely
    the conserving of institutions that are founded on stable categories
    of social distinction.  Contemporary conservatism in the United States
    sells itself on the liberal ideas that people like Burke combined into
    an uneasy amalgam with the traditional conservatism of hierarchy and
    authority, but that is not the normal understanding of conservatism
    in most of the world and most of history.  In that sense, Foucault's
    theory takes its place in a wider family of anti-institutional social
    movements.
    
    Theories of institutions routinely overgeneralize from particular
    circumstances, and Foucault, being French, is overgeneralizing from
    the history of institutions in France.  This includes the machinery
    of representation and regulation that I described above, and it also
    includes Catholic confession.  The framework of categories that these
    institutions impose in society are not the walls of a jail; quite the
    contrary, they are the raw material from which people are made: their
    conceptions of themselves, their identities in relation to others,
    their rituals, and so on.  For Foucault, the traditional institutions
    of conservative society are perfectly continuous with the extractive
    apparatus of absolutist rule, which in turn is perfectly continuous
    with the reformist state that intervenes in the life of the populace
    to inculcate hygeine, nutrition, morality, and much else.  Each of
    these social projects achieves its goals by inserting its ways into
    the bodies, minds, and architecture of the populace, all of which
    would remain self-propelling to a degree even if the bureaucracies
    that administer them were to disappear tomorrow.  That is what
    institutions are.
    
    The challenge is to construct a theory of the individual against
    that background.  Foucault paints a picture of impersonal historical
    processes inserting ever-more-invasive forms of rationality into
    the fine details of people's lives.  Law, medicine, the penal system,
    psychoanalysis -- all of these are ways of reaching ever more deeply
    into people's selves, bringing knowledge of them out into the open,
    reconstructing that knowledge in a rationalized form, and then
    turning the rationalized knowledge into institutions that monitor
    and intervene in their own particular area of life.  The institutions
    that result succeed only by reconstructing people's conceptions
    of themselves and the way they live their lives.  The medical system
    induces people to wait in waiting rooms, fill out paperwork, submit
    to medical procedures, reveal information about themselves, swallow
    pills, administer procedures on themselves under doctor's orders,
    pay attention to medical reports in the media, and so on.  People
    are induced to play their part and to intertwine themselves with the
    system.  This is what Foucault means by the "production of subjects".
    The "subject" is the person who engages with the places and people
    of medicine both inwardly and outwardly: identities and interactions,
    concepts and practices, knowledge and representation.
    
    The problem comes when he tries to explain what's left over --
    what there is to a human person other than the subjectivity that
    is prescribed by institutions.  Critics will object that Foucault's
    version of the human person, like Parsons', is oversocialized: he
    can tell us who the institution thinks you are, but that is not the
    same as telling us who *you* think you are.  True, your conception
    of yourself is indeed shaped and organized by the institution to
    a considerable degree.  True, your mental understanding of things,
    however critical-minded, is rendered somewhat superfluous by the
    matrix of bodily practices into which you've been inserted -- you
    may not like it, but you do it anyway.  True, the whole purpose
    of institutional power is to arrange society so that you have no
    practical option but to play your part in the drama that it scripts.
    But these are only partial answers.  Foucault understands perfectly
    well that every institution has fissures.  He is quite clear that
    the web of practices that comprise an institution is not seamless,
    and that the whole system is only held together by a continuous
    and diverse stream of interventions by various parties with various
    motives.
    
    Above all he emphasizes that institutions encounter resistance.  The
    core of the problem with Foucault's theory is that he provides, and
    can provide, no serious theory of what "resistance" means.  Foucault
    is very concerned with the word "power".  He wants to replace a
    conception of social order as the conscious domination of a sovereign
    with the impersonal, self-replicating capabilities of an institution.
    Institutions are spread out.  Nobody is in charge of them.  They may
    include organizations that have directors and presidents, but those
    job titles correspond to forms of subjectivity that the institution
    produces in the same way that it produces everything else.  Power,
    therefore, is "capillary": it is to be found not in the citadel but on
    the ground, in the detailed work by which it is lived in the relations
    and interactions among people.  And that is where resistance is to be
    found as well.  Power is power because something resists it, Foucault
    and his followers would argue.  Otherwise there would be no need for
    it.  But this won't do.  It defines resistance purely in terms of
    power -- more an expression of power's paranoia than a position in
    its own right -- and gives it no independent existence at all.  Power
    is generative, and resistance is simply one more of its generative
    effects.  In particular, resistance cannot be understood as a form
    of subjectivity, because all subjectivity is held to flow from power.
    
    Resistance for Foucault is thus a purely negative principle.  Nor
    is this an accident; it is the essence of Foucault's Nietzschean
    philosophy.  Just as Marx foresaw the immanent laws of capitalist
    development bringing about their own final negation through the
    forces that they themselves generated, so likewise the resistance that
    Foucault saw power generating in every greater profusion along an ever
    greater multiplicity of fronts is supposed to bring about the final
    dissolution of power and thus the final dissolution of the subjects
    that it has produced.  By exploding all categories and rejecting
    all essences, we are going to find freedom beyond our suturing
    into institutions.  It is a hard position to argue for, since the
    liberation it seeks cannot be named; to specify it in detail would
    simply set in motion the impersonal machinery of power once more.
    It is, ultimately, a kind of faith -- faith that the comprehensive
    dismantling of the personality leads to freedom and not to madness.
    It is an easy faith to hold if you believe that madness is simply
    an institution like an other, a label which some people are assigned,
    a category to which they conform and are conformed.  But it is not
    a faith for which we have any evidence.  And lacking evidence, all
    that Foucault has really given us is a picture of the social world
    operating at absolute zero, utterly colonized by institutions except
    for the white noise that crackles in the background.
    
    An intellectual system gets its power largely by making alternatives
    unthinkable, and in Foucault's case the effect is straightforward:
    anything that happens in society can easily be recast as one more
    effect of power.  The only remedy for this kind of hermetic closure
    is engagement with reality, and to that end it will be helpful
    to consider an application of Foucault's theory, a paper by Mark
    Poster (his best, in my view) about the nature of computer databases.
    The folk view of computer databases is that they are containers
    of digital symbols -- ones and zeroes -- some of which refer to
    particular individuals in society.  Databases are dangerous, on this
    view, because powerful bureaucracies can use the information to come
    around and intervene in people's lives.  The idea is that people are
    perfectly self-defining until that day when the authorities decide
    to oppress them.  Poster rejects this view, arguing instead that
    databases can only be understood in terms of the institutions that
    they support.  People's lives don't get represented in databases
    at random; rather, databases encode (if not always correctly) facts
    whose categories an institution defines.  Medical databases are
    part of the medical system, and so are you.  Information about you
    resides in medical databases because you are a patient -- that is,
    a particular category of person who is defined by the institution
    of medicine -- and it remains connected to you for the same reason.
    
    You can think of a database as simply one element in a chain that
    binds you together with other sorts of people and places into a larger
    system.  The lines of power flow through your body, and then through
    the medical offices, and then through the database, and then through
    the public health system, and so forth until they flow once again
    through your body and the circuit is complete.  From that perspective,
    it makes no sense to think of privacy in terms of being left alone.
    The medical system doesn't come beating down your door; rather, you
    go over to the doctor's office and submit yourself to the medical
    system of your own free will.  You are intertwined with that database,
    and central to that intertwining is the system of categories that
    defines both the indices of the database, your health and illness as
    a patient in the mind of the medical system, and your own understanding
    of yourself as a participant in the system (e.g., as a person with
    high cholesterol).  Of course, these different manifestations of
    the medical categories need not be exactly the same; databases don't
    always capture the full meaning of the concepts that they encode,
    and medical concepts do not always survive translation from medical
    language to the vernacular.  But the institution of medicine,
    on Foucault's account, does not require that sort of seamlessness.
    It requires only that pressure be continually applied to reconstruct
    the patient more and more fully within the system of rationality that
    the medical system organizes and the database inscribes.
    
    This understanding of databases is certainly an improvement on the
    blurry understanding that it replaced.  But it still leaves a great
    deal to be desired.  For one thing, it does not tell us what to
    do about the problem -- it's not even clear about what the problem
    is.  If our existence as medical patients is wholly constituted by
    the medical system, save for the intrinsically undefinable static
    of "resistance", what exactly is wrong with the overall picture of
    medical databases that should motivate us to change it?  Nor does the
    Foucauldian story explain how databases came about.  The Foucauldian
    explanation would be that databases express the same impersonal
    rationality that also organizes large parts of our selves and lives.
    This is true in the sense that the main tradition of computer system
    design emerged as a means of automating existing bureaucracies; the
    whole point of this design practice is to inscribe an institution's
    existing categories into the database.  But this is too unitary
    an account of the actual development of these systems, all of which
    reflect a negotiated tension among different interests within the
    medical world.  Nor does it explain the serious collisions that occur
    when the rational visions inscribed in medical informatics systems
    encounter the mangle of practice in real clinics.  Despite its appeals
    to heterogeneity, Foucault's theory is the story of the expression
    of one principle throughout history, the impersonal yet single-minded
    force that institutes its multiplying categories within our lives.
    No other principles are even conceivable, and yet it is only through
    the contention among different principles that we can understand the
    actual course of history.  Backing off from Foucault's story does not
    mean returning to an unsocialized view of human beings as completely
    defined by their own already-autonomous goals.  But it does mean
    acknowledging agendas besides the ones that are generated by the
    mechanical workings of power.
    
    Alternative theories exist.  Driven partly by the conflict between
    the liberal and oversocialized views of the individual, sociologists
    have made several attempts to overcome the dichotomy that I described
    above.  One of these new institutionalisms, for example, directs our
    attention to the rough edges between different disciplinary agendas
    in organizations.  People are socialized to a degree through the
    cognitive patterns they acquire from their professional training,
    but these patterns hardly operate in a vacuum, free from abrasion
    by incompatible systems of thought.  Other theories have observed
    simply that people have multiple, incompatible worldviews that they
    shift among, depending on which one makes most sense or appears most
    strategic in a given setting.  This kind of multiplicity is compatible
    with Foucault's theory, which does admit that people are incorporated
    within multiple institutions that are not necessarily continuous
    with one another; what is missing in Foucault's theory is a positive
    theory of the person who transcends those multiple standpoints, or
    synthesizes them, or shifts among them, or holds them at some degree
    of critical distance.
    
    I find especially striking the contrast between Foucault's theory and
    that of Commons.  For Commons there is no mystery about the formation
    of subjects: people are indeed formed by the institutions in which
    they participate, but they are formed not as individuals remade in the
    institution's image but collectively as members of the social groups
    that the institution defines.  An institution such as the market,
    the educational system, or the church define a complex of social
    roles, a space of practicable goals, a repertoire of strategies, and
    so on.  The participants in the institution come together and keep it
    working as a going concern -- as a business in a literal sense, since
    the institution needs to keep serving the practical goals that keep
    people voluntarily bound to it.  Along the way, employees as a group
    develop their collective interests, collective knowledge, collective
    identities, and so on.  Likewise patients as a group, teachers as
    a group, and every group that is defined by one of the constitutive
    social roles of an institution.
    
    In this sense institutions define classes, and the history of
    institutions is largely the history of the process by which every
    class ascends, organizes, and causes its own practices to be inscribed
    into the law.  Examples abound: the labor movement, the consumer
    movement, the patients' rights movement, employers' associations,
    democratizing movements in religion, and many others.  The mangle of
    practices that organize the day-to-day activities of an institution's
    members are, for Commons, effectively contracts that interest groups
    negotiate among themselves.  The point is not necessarily that each
    group forms associations, elects delegates, convenes with the other
    groups' delegates around a table, hashes out language in all-night
    bargaining sessions, goes on strike for better wages, and so on.
    That is a stereotype even of union bargaining, much less of bargaining
    in other spheres of society.  The operating rules of an institution
    evolve over time as practical knowledge grows and a multitude of
    practical situations are worked through by the parties involved.
    Group solidarity is not a given, but neither is it necessarily
    measured by the formal displays of legislatures and demonstrations.
    Law is central to the development of institutions, but more as its
    culmination than its substance.
    
    Commons' theory reconciles the tension between the individual and
    the institution that has organized so much of Western intellectual
    history.  Individuals are largely formed in their thoughts, actions,
    strategies, knowledge, and goals by the institutions in which they
    participate, but no longer are the institutions understood as foreign
    invaders, much less as impersonal forces that seek only to deepen
    their own power.  Interests contend, and institutions evolve not
    according to any predetermined teleology but through the negotiated
    evolution of working rules.  Commons' theory is a political economy
    as well as a theory of subjects, and I would argue that everything
    that is true in Foucault's theory was already present in Commons'.
    Of course, Foucault has drawn attention to some new issues within the
    horizon of institutional analysis that Commons had described.  Commons
    was not concerned with issues of representation, for example.  He was
    concerned with work practices and their development, but not with the
    embodiment of that work.  He would probably not have seen the point.
    Foucault cares about those things because he sees individual human
    beings as the passive objects of the manipulations of power.  Commons,
    on the other hand, sees individual human beings as members of social
    groups that succeed or fail in their collective strivings to establish
    a place for themselves in the social order.  While representation
    and embodiment could probably be reconstructed as topics against
    that different background, they would end up being different topics.
    
    The point is not that Commons was a collectivist in any radical
    sense.  He was not a Marxist.  He was a Christian and persuaded of
    our individual value and fate.  Yet he saw that individuals make their
    contribution to history through the roles they play in the development
    of institutions.  Perhaps the greatest flaw in his theory is that
    he took collective action too fully for granted, and did not analyze
    the specific roles that individuals do play in institutions.  His
    individual was not entrepreneurial, was not in fact even especially
    deliberative.  His central value was democratic culture (which has
    nothing to do with the ancient authoritarian stereotypes of democracy
    as the rule of mobs and the tyranny of mindless majorities) and he
    wanted to facilitate the emergence of an institutional order that
    realized democratic values.  I don't know if he saw that order as
    inevitable, but living through the Progressive and New Deal era he
    did think that he saw it happening before him.
    
    In writing about how-to's, I am trying to fill in the missing pieces
    of the picture.  The place of the individual in institutions has
    been a well-kept secret, despite going on so massively in our own
    day-to-day activities, both because of the nature of institutions
    and because of the impasses in our theories about them.  The concept
    of socialization, for example, contains a crucial ambiguity.  If we
    think of institutions as requiring mere compliance, then the purpose
    of socalization is to train people to conform to the rules.  Any old
    system of ideas will suffice, so long as the people conform.  Foucault
    goes further, arguing that institutions require a continual revelation
    of ever-deeper facts about the individual, whether through scientific
    research or epidemiology or psychiatry, turning individuals inside out
    to entwine them more profoundly in the circuitry of power.  Commons,
    writing in the context of industrial relations in the early 20th
    century, was concerned with the practical skills involved in doing the
    job and with the contracts that define how those skills are allocated
    and fitted together.  Commons studied going concerns.
    
    What has gone unexamined all around is the skill by which individuals
    use institutions to get what they want -- what's called, in a precise-
    sounding but empty way, agency.  Anybody who has dealt with an HMO can
    relate to the idea that getting medical care is a skill -- not just in
    complying with the complexities of the system, and not especially in
    subverting the system, but taking hold of the levers of the system to
    reveal nonobvious choices, uncover nonobvious information, and so on.
    Likewise, anybody who has gone to graduate school can recall the time
    when they did not understand the system, when people around them were
    busily engaged in career-furthering activities whose logic was not at
    all clear.  If you believe that socialization simply means learning
    to comply with external demands or simply learning to believe in the
    legitimacy of the institution's norms, then this kind of career skill
    is beside the point.  It plays no obvious role in explaining social
    order, and in fact it probably sounds dangerous from the point of view
    of maintaining social order.
    
    I contend that the vacuum of information around career skills is
    a drag on the efficacy of most institutions.  Career skills are
    not simply a variety of procedural knowledge; having applied those
    skills, one starts to occupy a new standpoint from which new kinds
    of knowledge become visible.  It is only in working the institution
    under your own steam, in pursuit of your own goals, that you learn
    how the institution really works in the first place.  How, then,
    do institutions really work?  As a rule of thumb, any institutional
    theory lacks a serious theory of individual agency unless it explains
    the dynamic relationship between collective cognition and social
    networks.  The world changes, and careers are made by articulating the
    changes and building social networks around them.  This is true across
    a wide range of institutions, and it is strikingly true even among
    social groups like medical patients that we conventionally understand
    as passive individuals.
    
    To be sure, those conventional understandings are not illusory;
    they simply overgeneralize from the pathological situation in which
    medical patients (for example) lack the skills and associational forms
    they need to be properly organized in pursuit of their collective
    interests.  Even the language of collective interests misleads us, so
    deeply has it been shaped by radical conceptions of the "masses" as
    a blurry group whose political success is determined solely by their
    solidarity.  In this way collectivist thought has generally rejected
    the appeal to individual initiative that I am advocating.  That is
    because they see individual initiative purely against the background
    of market institutions that place undifferentiated individuals in
    pure price competition against one another.  Class solidarity, on
    that view, is founded precisely on recognizing and amplifying that
    group homogeneity.
    
    An alternative perspective is that careers are made -- within groups
    as well as between them -- by taking the initiative to articulate
    a particular emerging issue.  Differentiation is the key in building
    an effective association for collective action, just as it is the
    key to avoiding price competition in the market.  But differentiation
    here does not mean artificially introducing differences for their
    own sake, but rather identifying one's own unique contribution.  This
    is a social skill whose prototype has historically been the business
    enterpreneur, and for that reason it is often called entrepreneurship
    in a more general sense.  Generations of individuals in the depths
    of institutions have suffered lectures on the necessity of being
    entrepreneurial, even though few of those lectures provide any
    useful guidance about what this means or how one should go about it.
    Enterpreneurialism is often treated as a character trait, and its lack
    as a defect of character, precisely because the nature of the skill
    -- as with most skills -- is largely unarticulated even by the people
    who do it.  Even books about entrepreneurship typically start late
    in the process, taking for granted that the entrepreneur possesses
    a network and an idea and then settling down to the details of
    funding and hiring and marketing.  It is very common for textbooks to
    skip the first few chapters, the ones that the author has forgotten
    ever not knowing, and the first few chapters of society's textbook of
    entrepreneurialism likewise tend to be missing.
    
    As a result of these silences, lectures about being entrepreneurial
    are often misunderstood: people watch the finagling that goes into
    starting a new business -- a process that one entrepreneur described
    to me as convincing ten people that the other nine are already
    on board -- and they recoil, seeing entrepreneurship as competely
    unrelated to their own conception of themselves.  What they don't
    realize, because nobody has ever told them, is that the essence of
    entrepreneurship lies much earlier in the process, in the recognition
    of themes that are emerging in the thinking of numerous people
    in your social world.  You can recognize those themes by meeting
    people at parties, or attending professional conferences, or going
    bar-hopping, or reading books -- any mechanism that provides you with
    surveillance about the thinking of a broad sample of people in your
    social group.
    
    This claim -- that enterpreneurship is a general phenomenon and not
    restricted just to starting new businesses in the market -- throws new
    light on the nature of institutions in general.  A common intuition
    in conservative theories is that institutions, though often venerable,
    do not define human nature.  We need to eat, sleep, work, socialize,
    raise children, and so on, and these broad categories of needs
    are universal and exist prior to any specific institutional form. 
    Institutions, from this perspective, bring order to the provision
    of biological needs.  Institutions provide a cognitive framework
    for sharing knowledge, an economic framework for production, and a
    moral framework so that people can discipline themselves to provide
    for their needs rather than collapsing into dissolution.  If so,
    then perhaps the role of social networks in entrepreneurship is
    also prior to institutions and then organized and given form within
    them.  We should not be surprised to see family resemblances among
    institutions in different times and places, as well as differences
    in the effectiveness of institutions, given that each institution
    exists to subserve one or more of a limited repertoire of underlying
    functions.  Perhaps entrepreneurship is one of these functions -- not
    an end in itself but an intrinsic principle of social functioning in
    a world of any dynamism.
    
    None of this is to exonerate the less attractive features of the
    conservative philosophy of institutions, such as its comfort with
    injustice in the name of tradition and its willingness to trade
    off the dysfunctions of existing institutions against the hazards
    of changing them.  It is more of a thought experiment.  After all,
    conservatism is no more helpful than the progressive theories of
    Commons when it comes to explaining the conditions of entrepreneurship.
    So long as liberty is conceived in negative terms, purely as the
    lack of intervention by the state, it is hard to understand what
    makes for entrepreneurship in markets, much less in the broad range of
    institutions generally.  Entrepreneurship has institutional conditions
    of several sorts, and complacency about the institutional legacies of
    the past is probably not among them.  In a dynamic world, institutions
    are necessarily remade in every generation -- not just restaffed,
    as retirees leave and new recruits occupy their offices, but remade,
    as the mechanisms that mediate the full range of human relationships
    are reinvented in the practical, ideological, infrastructural, and
    economic context of the times.
    
    The age-old confusion about the relationship between individuals
    and institutions recurs in the chronic unclarity in the literature
    about the relationship between entrepreneurship and group interests.
    Entrepreneurs are stereotyped as individualists who break out of
    institutional molds, assemble new networks of people and practices,
    and allow those new networks to settle into place.  Entrepreneurs,
    on this view, are pioneers who clear new land and then move on.
    But entrepreneurship is something much larger than that.  It has
    an intellectual dimension.  And most entrepreneurs work within
    the institutional terrain provided by particular social groups --
    for example professions, academia, large companies, the government,
    innovative regions such as Silicon Valley, and so on.  Social groups
    like the ones that Commons describes engage in collective cognition,
    and entrepreneurship is one way they do that.  New ideas come to fore
    because entrepreneurial individuals in the group pioneer them -- not
    just by writing them down but by assembling networks of people who
    know about them.  Social groups likewise adopt new strategies because
    individual entrepreneurs within them have taken the trouble to
    assemble consensus around those strategies.  Consensus in this context
    does not refer to the procedures of group deliberation, but rather
    to the putting-together of a network that is capable of winning an
    argument in a democratic forum.  Entrepreneurs do these things as
    an investment: they expect that their issue will grow, so that the
    network they begin assembling will acquire its own momentum with time,
    leaving them in a privileged position as the person in the middle
    who knows all the players and tracks all the action.  They may intend
    to make money, or to promote a social vision, or to gain a possibly
    unforeseen range of collateral benefits from their central location.
    
    Reviewing the history of institutions that I sketched at the outset,
    it seems to me that much of that history remains unwritten.  Because
    so much of the practical work of entrepreneurship is taken for
    granted, and because so much of that work is hidden in the tacit logic
    of harmless-sounding social interactions, many social phenomena are
    effectively treated as magic by everyone involved.  Histories too
    often tell of major social figures who become interested in a given
    topic and then show up in the next paragraph working in the White
    House or starting a company, as if anyone at all could have decided
    one morning to attain those positions, or as if their ascent expressed
    their unique personalities and not the things they did in the material
    world.
    
    This situation is starting to change now, happily, as theories
    of entrepreneurship (Michel Callon, Mark Casson, etc) become more
    sophisticated.  Yet the theme of enterpreneurship has not been
    integrated back into the framework of social thought, renewing
    categories of social analysis that otherwise remain underpowered.
    This, it seems to me, is the most important area of research that
    is opening up before us, and not just because of its intellectual
    interest but because of its material consequences for people's lives.
    Institutions that merely socialize people do in fact trap them into
    the sort of passive confusion that Foucault takes for granted even
    as he rails nebulously against it.  Institutions that provide the
    conditions of democratic leadership for all their participants, on
    the other hand, do not simply socialize people into riding in the back
    seat but take the risk of handing them the keys.  Robust institutions
    can deal with the consequences of unleashing fully drawn human beings.
    Those that cannot are not worth being conserved.
    
    References
    
    Phil Agre, In defense of how-to's, MS, 13 December 2001.  Available at
    <http://commons.somewhere.com/rre/2001/RRE.notes.and.recommenda3.html>
    
    Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolutist State, London: NLB, 1974.
    
    Harold J. Berman, Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western
    Legal Tradition, Harvard University Press, 1983.
    
    Michel Callon, ed, The Laws of the Markets, Oxford: Blackwell, 1998.
    
    Michael Carrithers, Steven Collins, and Steven Lukes, eds, The
    Category of the Person: Anthropology, Philosophy, History, Cambridge:
    Cambridge University Press, 1985.
    
    Mark Casson, The Entrepreneur: An Economic Theory, Oxford: Robertson,
    1982.
    
    Mark Casson, Entrepreneurship and Business Culture, Aldershot, UK:
    Elgar, 1995.
    
    John R. Commons, Legal Foundations of Capitalism, New York: Macmillan,
    1924.
    
    John R. Commons, The Economics of Collective Action, Madison:
    University of Wisconsin Press, 1970.  Originally published in 1950.
    
    Thomas Ertman, Birth of the Leviathan: Building States and Regimes
    in Medieval and Early Modern Europe, Cambridge: Cambridge University
    Press, 1997.
    
    Andrew Feenberg, Critical Theory of Technology, New York: Oxford
    University Press, 1991.
    
    Michel Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaeology of Medical
    Perception, translated by A. M. Sheridan Smith, New York: Pantheon,
    1973.
    
    Mark Granovetter, Economic action and social structure: The problem
    of embeddedness, American Journal of Sociology 91(3), 1985, pages
    481-510.
    
    Judith Gregory, Sorcerer's Apprentice: Creating the Electronic
    Health Record, Reinventing Medical Records and Patient Care, doctoral
    dissertation, Department of Communication, University of California,
    San Diego, 2000.
    
    Friedrich A. Hayek, The Counter-Revolution of Science: Studies on the
    Abuse of Reason, Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1952.
    
    Friedrich A. Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order, Chicago:
    University of Chicago Press, 1963.
    
    Johan Heilbron, The Rise of Social Theory, translated by Sheila Gogol,
    Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995.
    
    Talcott Parsons,  The Structure of Social Action: A Study in Social
    Theory with Special Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers,
    Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1949.
    
    Mark Poster, Databases as discourse, or, Electronic interpellations,
    in David Lyon and Elia Zureik, eds, Computers, Surveillance, and
    Privacy, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996.
    
    Walter W. Powell and Paul J. DiMaggio, eds, The New Institutionalism
    in Organizational Analysis, Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
    1991.
    
    James C. Scott, Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve
    the Human Condition Have Failed, New Haven: Yale University Press,
    1998.
    
    Ann Swidler, Culture in action: Symbols and strategies, American
    Sociological Review 51(2), 1986, pages 273-286.
    
    Dennis H. Wrong, The oversocialized conception of man in modern
    sociology, American Sociological Review, 26(2), 1961, pages 183-193.
    
    Anton C. Zijdervald, The Institutional Imperative: The Value of
    Institutions in Contemporary Society, Amsterdam: Amsterdam University
    Press, 2000.
    
    end
    



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Wed Dec 19 2001 - 17:45:30 PST