[RRE]Machine Dreams

From: Phil Agre (pagreat_private)
Date: Mon Jun 25 2001 - 19:43:57 PDT

  • Next message: Phil Agre: "[RRE]hackers and cars"

    [Forwarded by permission and heavily reformatted.]
    
    =-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=
    This message was forwarded through the Red Rock Eater News Service (RRE).
    You are welcome to send the message along to others but please do not use
    the "redirect" option.  For information about RRE, including instructions
    for (un)subscribing, see http://dlis.gseis.ucla.edu/people/pagre/rre.html
    =-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=-=
    
    Date: Mon, 25 Jun 2001 09:39:33 -0500
    From: "Philip E. Mirowski" <pmirowsat_private>
    
    Machine Dreams:
    Economics Becomes a Cyborg Science
    
    Philip Mirowski
    
    Cambridge University Press
    
    0-521-77283-4 (hardcover)
    0-521-77526-4 (paperback)
    
    Table of Contents
    
    1 Cyborg Agonistes
    2 Some Cyborg Genealogies; or, How the Demon Got its Bots
    3 John von Neumann and the Cyborg Incursion into Economics
    4 The Military, the Scientists and the Revised Rules of the Game
    5 Do Cyborgs Dream of Efficient Markets?
    6 The Empire Strikes Back
    7 Core Wars
    8 Machines Who Think vs. Machines that Sell
    
    
    Chapter 1: Cyborg Agonistes
    
      A true war story is never moral.  It does not instruct, nor
      encourage virtue, nor suggest models of proper human behavior, nor
      restrain men from doing the things they have always done.  If a
      story seems moral, do not believe it.  If at the end of a war story
      you feel uplifted, or if you feel that some small bit of rectitude
      has been salvaged from the larger waste, then you have been made the
      victim of a very old and terrible lie.
         --Tim O'Brien, The Things They Carried
    
    The first thing you will notice is the light.  The florescent banks
    in the high ceiling are dimmed, so the light at eye level is dominated
    by the glowing screens set at intervals throughout the cavernous room.
    There are no windows, so the bandwidths have that cold otherworldly
    truncation.  Surfaces are in muted tones and matte colors, dampening
    unwanted reflections.  Some of the screens flicker with strings of
    digits the color and periodicity of traffic lights, but most beam
    the standard dayglo palette of pastels usually associated with CRT
    graphics.  While a few of the screens project their photons into
    the void, most of the displays are manned and womanned by attentive
    acolytes, their visages lit and their backs darkened like satellites
    parked in stationary orbits.  Not everyone is held in the thrall of
    the object of their attentions in the same manner.  A few jump up and
    down in little tethered dances, speaking into phones or mumbling at
    other electronic devices.  Some sit stock still, mesmerized, engaging
    their screen with slight movements of wrist and hand.  Others lean
    into their consoles, then away, as though their swaying might actually
    have some virtual influence upon the quantum electrodynamics coursing
    through their station and beyond, to other machines in other places
    in other similar rooms.  No one is apparently making anything, but
    everyone seems nonetheless furiously occupied.
    
    I. Rooms with a View
    
    Where is this place?  If it happened to be 1952, it would be Santa
    Monica, California, at a RAND study of the "man-machine interface"
    (Chapman et al, 1958).  If it were 1957, then it could only be one
    place: the SAGE (Semi-Automatic Ground Environment) Air Defense System
    run by the US Air Force.  By 1962, there were a few other such rooms,
    such as the SAGA room for war-gaming in the basement of the Pentagon
    (Allen, 1987).  If it were 1967 instead, there were many more such
    rooms scattered across the globe, one of the largest being the
    Infiltration Surveillance Center at Nakhom Phanom in Thailand, the
    command center of US Air Force Operation Igloo White (Edwards, 1996,
    pp.3, 106).  By 1977 there are many more such rooms, no longer only
    staffed by the military, but also by thousands of employees of large
    firms throughout the world: the SABRE airline reservation system of
    American Airlines (patterned upon SAGE); bank check and credit card
    processing centers (patterned upon that innovated by Bank of America);
    nuclear power station control rooms; the inventory control operation
    of the American Hospital Supply Corporation (McKenney, 1995).  In
    1987, a room like this could be found in any suburban shopping mall,
    with teenagers proleptically feeding quarters into arcade computer
    games.  It might also be located at the University of Arizona,
    where "experimental markets" are being conducted with undergraduates
    recruited with the help of money from the National Science Foundation.
    Alternatively, these closed rooms also could just as surely be found
    in the very pinnacles of high finance, in the tonier precincts of New
    York and London and Tokyo, with high-stakes traders of stocks, bonds
    and "derivatives" glued to their screens.  In those rooms, "masters of
    the universe" in pinstripe shirts and power suspenders make "killings"
    in semi-conscious parody of their khaki-clad precursors.  By 1997,
    with the melding of home entertainment centers with home offices
    and personal computers via the Internet (a lineal descendant of
    the Defense-funded ARPANET), any residential den or rec room could
    be refitted as a scaled-down simulacrum of any of the previous
    rooms.  It might be the temporary premises of one of the burgeoning
    'dot-com' startups which captured the imaginations of Generation X.
    It could even be promoted as the prototype classroom of the future.
    Increasingly, work in America at the turn of the millennium means
    serried ranks of Dilberts arrayed in cubicles staring at these
    screens.  I should perhaps confess I am staring at the glow now
    myself.  Depending upon how this text eventually gets disseminated,
    perhaps you also, dear reader, are doing likewise.
    
    These rooms are the "closed worlds" of our brave new world (Edwards,
    1996), the electronic surveillance and control centers which were
    the nexus of the spread of computer technologies and computer culture.
    They are closed in any number of senses.  In the first instance,
    there is the obviously artificial light: chaotic 'white' sunlight
    is kept to a minimum to control the frequencies and the reactions
    of the observers.  This is an ergonomically controlled environment,
    the result of some concerted engineering of the man-machine interface,
    in order to render the machines 'user-friendly' and their acolytes
    more predictable.  The partitioning off of the noise of the outer
    world brings to mind another sort of closure, that of thermodynamic
    isolation, as when Maxwell's Demon closes the door on slower gas
    molecules in order to make heat flow from a cooler to a warmer room,
    thus violating the second law of thermodynamics.  Then again, there
    is the type of closure that is more directly rooted in the algorithms
    that play across the screens, a closure that we shall encounter
    repeatedly in this book.  The first commandment of the trillions of
    lines of code that appear on the screens is that they halt; algorithms
    are closed and bounded, and (almost never) spin on forever, out of
    control.
    
    And then the rooms are closed in another fashion, one resembling
    Bentham's Panopticon: a hierarchical and pervasive surveillance which
    is experienced as an automatic and anonymous expression of power
    (Foucault, 1977).  The range of things which the occupants of the
    room can access, from your medical records to the purchases you made
    three years ago with your credit card, from your telephone calls to
    all the web pages you have visited, from your genealogy to your genome,
    consistently outstrips the paltry imagination of movies haunted by
    suggestions of paranoid conspiracies and fin-de-siecle science run
    amok (Bernstein, 1997).  Just as surely as death is the culmination
    of life, surveillance raises the spectre of counter-surveillance,
    of dissimulation, of penetration; and closure comes increasingly to
    resemble prophylaxis.  The language of viruses, worms and a myriad
    of other creepy-crawlies evokes the closure of a siege mentality, of
    quarantine, or perhaps the tomb.
    
    The closure of those rooms is also radically stark in that implacable
    conflicts of global proportions are frequently shrunk down to
    something far less than human scale, to the claustrophobic controlled
    play of pixilated symbols on screens.  The scale of phenomena seems to
    have become distended and promiscuously distributed.  As the computer
    scientist Joseph Weitzenbaum has once said, the avatars of artificial
    intelligence tend to describe "a very small part of what it means
    to be a human being and say that this is the whole".  He quotes
    the philosopher (and cheerleader for AI) Daniel Dennett as having
    insisted, "If we are to make further progress in Artificial
    Intelligence, we are going to have to give up our awe of living
    things" (in Baumgartner & Payr, 1995, p.259).  The quickest way to
    divest oneself of an awe for the living in the West is to imagine
    oneself surrounded instead by machines.  Whatever may have once
    been imagined the rich ambiguity of multiform experience, it seems
    enigmatic encounters and inconsistent interpretations can now only be
    expressed in this brave new world as information.  Ideas are conflated
    with things, and things like computers assume the status of ideas.
    
    And although there is the widespread notion that as the global
    reach of these rooms has been stretched beyond the wildest dreams of
    the medieval magus or Enlightenment philosophe, the denizens of the
    modern closed rooms seem to have grown more insular, less experienced,
    perhaps even a trifle solipsistic.  Closed rooms had held out the
    promise of infinite horizons; but the payoff has been... more closure.
    Who needs to venture any more into the inner city, the outer banks,
    the corridors of the Louvre, the sidewalks of mean streets?  Travel,
    real physical displacement, has become like everything else: you
    need special reservations and a pile of money to go experience the
    simulacra that the screen has already conditioned you to expect.
    More annual visitors to Boston seek out the mock-up of the fictional
    bar "Cheers" than view Bunker Hill or Harvard Yard.  Restaurants and
    museums and universities and corporations and Walden Pond are never
    quite as good as their web sites.  Cyberspace, once a new metaphor
    for spatial orientation, comes to usurp motion itself.  No, don't get
    around much any more.
    
    II. Where the Cyborgs Are
    
    Is this beginning to sound like just another pop sociology treatise on
    "being digital" or the "information superhighway" or "the second self"
    or denunciation of some nefarious cult of information (Roszak, 1994)?
    Calm your fears, dear reader.  What the world needs now is surely not
    another panegyric on the cultural evils of cyberspace.  Our whirlwind
    tour of a few clean, well-lighted places is intended to introduce,
    in a subliminal way, some of the themes that will structure a work
    situated more or less squarely within a distinctly despised genre,
    that of the history of economic thought.  The novelty for most readers
    will be to cross it with an older and rather more popular form of
    narrative, that of the war story.  The chronological succession of
    closed rooms is intended to serve as a synecdoche for a succession
    of the ways in which many economists have come to understand markets
    over roughly the same period, stretching from World War II to the end
    of the twentieth century.  For while these closed rooms begat little
    models of closed worlds, after the fashion of Plato's Cave, the
    world as we had found it has rapidly been transubstantiated into the
    architecture of the rooms.  Modes of thought and machines that think
    forged in British and American military settings by their attendant
    mobilized army of scientists in the 1940s rapidly made their way into
    both the natural and social sciences in the immediate postwar period,
    with profound consequences for both the content and organization of
    science.
    
    The thesis that a whole range of sciences have been transformed in
    this manner in the postwar period has come to have a name in the
    literature of the history and sociology of science, primarily due
    to the pioneering efforts of Donna Haraway: that name is "cyborg
    science".  Haraway (1991, 1997) uses the term to indicate something
    profound that has happened to biology and to social theory and
    cultural conceptions of gender.  It has been applied to computer
    development and industrial organization by Andy Pickering (1995a;
    1997, 1999).  Ian Hacking (1998) has drawn attention to the
    connections of cyborgs to Canguilhem and Foucault.  Explication of
    the cyborg character of thermodynamics and information theory was
    pioneered by Katherine Hayles (1990b), who has now devoted prodigious
    work to explicating their importance for the early cyberneticians
    (1994;1995a; 1999).  Paul Edwards' (1996) was the first serious
    across-the-board survey of the military's conceptual influence
    on the development of the computer, although Kenneth Flamm (1988)
    had pioneered the topic in the economics literature of industrial
    organization.  Steve Heims (1991) documented the initial attempts of
    the first cyberneticians to reach out to social scientists in search
    of a Grand Unified Teleological theory.  Evelyn Fox Keller (1995) has
    surveyed how the gene has assumed the trappings of military command;
    and Lily Kay (1995, 1997a) has performed the invaluable service of
    showing in detail how all the above played themselves out in the
    development of molecular biology.  Although all of these authors
    have at one time or another indicated an interest in economic ideas,
    what has been wanting in all of this work so far is a commensurate
    consideration of the role of economists in this burgeoning
    trans-disciplinary formation.  Economists were present at the creation
    of the cyborg sciences, and as one would expect, the cyborg sciences
    have returned the favor by serving in turn to remake the economic
    orthodoxy in their own image.  It is my intention in this work
    to provide that complementary argument, and to document just in
    what manner and to what extent economics at the end of the second
    millennium has become a cyborg science; and to speculate how this will
    shape the immediate future.
    
    Just how serious has the cyborg incursion been for economics?  Given
    that in all likelihood most economists have no inkling what "cyborgs"
    are, or will have little familiarity with the historical narrative
    which follows, the question must be confronted squarely.  There are
    two preliminary responses to this challenge: one short, yet readily
    accessible to anyone familiar with the modern economics literature;
    and the other, necessarily more involved, requiring a fair complement
    of historical sophistication.  The short answer starts out with the
    litany that every tyro economist memorizes in their first introductory
    course.  Question: What is economics about?  Answer: The optimal
    allocation of scarce resources to given ends.  This catechism was
    promulgated in the 1930s, about the time that neoclassicism was poised
    to displace rival schools of economic thought in the American context,
    and represented the canonical image of trade as the shifting about
    of given endowments so as to maximize an independently given utility
    function.  While this phrase still may spring effortlessly to the
    lips-- this, after all, is the function of a catechism-- nevertheless,
    pause and reflect how poorly this captures the primary concerns
    of neoclassical economists nowadays.  Nash equilibrium, strategic
    uncertainty, decision theory, path dependence, network externalities,
    evolutionary games, principal-agent dilemmas, no trade theorems,
    asymmetric information, paradoxes of noncomputability, ...  Static
    allocation has taken a back seat to all manner of issues concerning
    agents' capacities to deal with various market situations in a
    cognitive sense.  It has even once again become fashionable to speak
    with confidence of the indispensable role of "institutions", although
    this now means something profoundly different than it did in the
    earlier heyday of the American Institutionalist school of economics.
    This is a drastic change from the 1930s through the 50s, when it
    was taboo to speculate about mind, and all marched proudly under the
    banner of behaviorism; and society was thought to spring fully-formed
    from the brow of an isolated economic man.  So what is economics
    really about these days?  The New Modern Answer: The economic agent as
    a processor of information.
    
    This is the first, and only the most obvious, hallmark of the epoch of
    economics as a cyborg science.  The other attributes will require more
    prodigious documentation and explication.
    
    III. The Natural Sciences and the History of Economics
    
    The other, more elaborate, answer to the query concerning the
    relevance of cyborgs for economics requires some working familiarity
    with the history of neoclassical economics.  In a previous book
    entitled More Heat than Light (1989a), I argued that the genesis of
    the supposed "simultaneous discovery" of neoclassicism in the 1870s
    could be traced to the enthusiasm for "energetics" growing out of the
    physics of the mid-19th century.  As was admitted by William Stanley
    Jevons, Leon Walras, Vilfredo Pareto, Francis Edgeworth and Irving
    Fisher, "utility" was patterned upon potential energy in classical
    mechanics, as were their favored mathematics of extremum principles.
    Their shared vision of the operation of the market (and the mind of
    the agent, if they were willing to make this commitment) was avowedly
    mechanical in an eminently physical sense of that term.  Their shared
    prescription for rendering economics a science was to imitate the
    best science they knew, right down to its characteristic mathematical
    formalisms.  It was a science of causality, rigid determinism and
    preordained order; in other words, it was physics prior to the
    second law of thermodynamics, a science most assuredly innocent
    of the intellectual upheavals beginning at the turn of the century
    and culminating in the theories of quantum mechanics and statistical
    thermodynamics.
    
    Some readers of that volume demurred that, although it was undeniably
    the case that important figures such as Jevons and Walras and Fisher
    cited physics as an immediate source of their inspiration, this still
    did not square with the neoclassical economics with which economists
    were familiar in the 20th century.  Indeed, a book by Bruna Ingrao
    and Giorgio Israel (1990) asserted that the impact of physics upon
    neoclassical economics was attenuated by the 1930s, precisely at
    the moment when it underwent substantial mathematical development
    and began its serious ascendancy.  Others have insisted that a whole
    range of orthodox models, from the modern Walrasian tradition to
    game theory, betray no inspiration whatsoever from physics.  The
    historiographical problem which these responses highlight is the lack
    of willingness to simultaneously examine the history of economics and
    the history of the natural sciences as jointly evolving historical
    entities, and not as fixed monolithic bodies of knowledge driven
    primarily by their internally-defined questions, whose interactions
    with other sciences can only be considered as irrelevant rhetoric
    in whatever era in which they may have occurred.  If you avert your
    gaze from anything other than the narrowly-conceived entity called
    the 'economy', then you will never understand the peripatetic path of
    American economics in the 20th century.
    
    This book could thus be regarded as the third installment in
    my ongoing project to track the role and impact of the natural
    sciences upon the structure and content of the orthodox tradition
    in economics which is perhaps inaccurately but conventionally dubbed
    "neoclassical".  The first installment of this history was published
    in 1989 as More Heat than Light, and was concerned with the period
    from classical political economy up to the 1930s, stressing the role
    of physics in the "marginalist revolution".  The second installment
    would comprise a series of papers co-authored over the 1990s with
    Wade Hands and Roy Weintraub, which traced the story of the rise to
    dominance of neoclassical price theory in America from early in the
    century up through the 1960s.  The present volume takes up the story
    from the rise of the cyborg sciences, primarily though not exclusively
    during World War II in America, and then traces their footprint upon
    some important postwar developments in economics, such as highbrow
    neoclassical price theory, game theory, rational expectations theory,
    theories of institutions and mechanism design, the nascent program
    of "bounded rationality", computational economics, "artificial
    economies", "autonomous agents", and experimental economics.  Since
    many of these developments are frequently regarded as antithetical to
    one another, or possibly movements bent upon rejection of the prior
    Walrasian orthodoxy, it will be important to discern the ways in which
    there is a profound continuity between their sources of inspiration
    and those of the earlier generations of neoclassical economics.
    
    One source of continuity is that economists, especially those seeking
    a scientific economics, have always been inordinately fascinated by
    machines.  Francois Quesnay's theory of circulation was first realized
    as a pump and some tubes of tin; only later did it reappear in
    abstract form as the Tableau Oeconomique.  Simon Schaffer has argued
    that "Automata were apt images of the newly disciplined bodies of
    military systems in early modern Europe...  Real connections were
    forged between these endeavors to produce a disciplined workforce,
    an idealized workspace, and an automatic man" (1999, pp.135, 144).
    It has been argued that the conception of natural order in British
    classical political economy was patterned upon the mechanical
    feedback mechanisms observed in clocks, steam engine governors, and
    the like (Mayr, 1976).  William Stanley Jevons, as we shall discuss
    below in Chapter 2, proudly compared the rational agent to a machine.
    Irving Fisher (1965) actually built a working model of cisterns
    and mechanical floats to illustrate his conception of economic
    equilibrium.  Many of those enthralled with the prospect that the
    laws of energy would ultimately unite the natural and social sciences
    looked to various engines and motors for their inspiration (Rabinbach,
    1990).  However, as Norbert Wiener so presciently observed at the
    dawn of the Cyborg Era: "If the seventeenth and the early eighteenth
    centuries are the age of clocks, the later eighteenth and nineteenth
    centuries constitute the age of steam engines, the present time is
    the age of communication and control" (1961, p.39).  Natural order for
    economists coming of age after WWII is still exemplified by a machine;
    it is just that the manifestation of the machine has changed: it is
    now the computer.  "It may be hard for younger economists to imagine,
    but nearly until midcentury it was not unusual for a theorist
    using mathematical techniques to begin with a substantial apology,
    explaining that this approach need not assume that humans are
    automatons deprived of free will" (Baumol, 2000, p.23).  Cyborg love
    means never having to say you're sorry.  Machine rationality and
    machine regularities are the constants in the history of neoclassical
    economics; it is only the innards of the machine that have changed
    from time to time.
    
    There is another, somewhat more contingent common denominator.  The
    history of economics has been persistently swept by periodic waves of
    immigrants from the natural sciences.  The first phase, that of the
    1870s through the turn of the century, was the era of a few trained
    engineers and physicists seeking to impose some analytical structure
    upon the energetic metaphors which were so prevalent in their culture.
    The next wave of entry came in the 1930s, prompted both by the Great
    Depression's contraction of career possibilities for scientists, and
    the great forced emigration of scientists from Europe to America due
    to persecution and the disruptions of war.  Wartime exigencies induced
    physicists to engage in all sorts of new activities under rubrics
    such as "operations research".  We shall encounter some of these
    more illustrious souls in the chapters below.  The third phase of
    scientific Diaspora is happening right now.  The end of the Cold War
    and its attendant shifts in the funding of scientific research has
    had devastating impact upon physics, and upon the career patterns
    of academic science in general (Slaughter & Rhoades, 1996; National
    Science Board, 1995; Gruner et al, 1996; Ziman, 1994).  Increasingly,
    physicists left to their own devices have found that economics (or
    perhaps more correctly, finance) has proven a relatively accommodating
    safe haven in their time of troubles (Pimbley, 1997; Baker, 1999;
    Bass, 1999; MacKenzie, 1999).  The ubiquitous contraction of physics
    and the continuing expansion of molecular biology has not only caused
    sharp redirections in careers, but also redirection of cultural
    images of what it means to be a successful science of epochal
    import.  In many ways, the rise of the cyborg sciences is yet another
    manifestation of these mundane considerations of funding and support;
    interdisciplinary research has become more akin to a necessary
    condition of survival in our brave new world than merely the province
    of a few dilettantes or Renaissance men; and the transformation of
    economic concepts described in subsequent chapters is as much an
    artifact of a newer generation of physicists, engineers and other
    natural scientists coming to terms with the traditions established
    by a previous generation of scientific interlopers dating from
    the Depression and WWII, as it is an entirely new direction in
    intellectual discourse.
    
    And, finally, there is one more source of the appearance of
    continuity.  I shall argue in Chapters 4 and 5 below that the first
    hesitant steps toward economics becoming a cyborg science were in fact
    made from a position situated squarely within the Walrasian tradition;
    these initially assumed the format of augmentation of the neoclassical
    agent with some capacities to deal with the fundamental "uncertainty"
    of economic life.  The primary historical site of this transitional
    stage was the RAND corporation and its ongoing contacts with the
    Cowles Commission.  Part of the narrative momentum of the story
    recounted herein will derive from the progressive realization that
    cyborgs and neoclassicals could not be so readily yoked one to
    another, or even cajoled to work in tandem, and that this has led to
    numerous tensions in fin-de-siecle orthodox economics.
    
    IV. Anatomy of a Cyborg
    
    So who or what are these cyborgs, that they have managed to spawn a
    whole brood of feisty new sciences?  A plausible reaction is to wonder
    whether the term more correctly belongs to science fiction, rather
    than to seriously practiced sciences as commonly understood.  For
    you, dear reader, it may invoke childhood memories of Star Wars or
    Star Trek; if you happen to be familiar with popular culture, it
    may conjure William Gibson's breakthrough novel Neuromancer (1984).
    Yet, as usual, science fiction does not anticipate as much as reflect
    prior developments in scientific thinking.  Upon consulting the
    Cyborg Handbook (Gray, 1995, p.29), one discovers that the term was
    invented in 1960 by Manfred Clynes and Nathan Kline in the scientific
    journal Astronautics (Clynes and Kline, 1995).  Manfred Clynes, an
    Austrian emigre (and merely the first of a whole raft of illustrious
    Austro-Hungarian emigres we shall encounter in this book), and one
    of the developers of the CAT scanner technology, had been introduced
    to cybernetics at Princeton in the 1950s, and was concerned about
    the relationship of the organism to its environment as a problem of
    the communication of information.  As he reports, "I thought it would
    be good to have a new concept, a concept of persons who can free
    themselves from the constraints of the environment to the extent
    that they wished.  And I coined this word cyborg" (Gray, 1995,
    p.47), short for cybernetic organism.  In a paper presented to an
    Air Force sponsored conference in 1960, Clynes and Kline assayed the
    possibilities of laboratory animals which were augmented in various
    ways in the interest of directly engaging in feedback stabilization
    and control of their metabolic environment.  The inquiry attracted
    the attention of NASA, which was worried about the effects of long
    term exposure to weightlessness and artificial environments in space.
    NASA then commissioned a Cyborg Study, which produced a report in May
    1963, surveying all manner of technologies to render astronauts more
    resilient to the rigors of space exploration, such as cardiovascular
    modules, hypothermia drugs, artificial organs, and the like.
    
    This incident establishes the precedence of use of the term in the
    scientific community; but it does little to define a stable referent.
    In the usage we will favor herein, it denotes not so much the study
    of a specific creature or organism as a set of regularities observed
    in a number of sciences which had their genesis in the immediate
    postwar period, sciences such as information theory, molecular biology,
    cognitive science, neuropsychology, computer science, artificial
    intelligence, operations research, systems ecology, immunology,
    automata theory, chaotic dynamics and fractal geometry, computational
    mechanics, sociobiology, artificial life, and last but not least,
    game theory.  Most of these sciences shared an incubation period in
    close proximity to the transient phenomenon called "cybernetics".
    While none of the historians cited above manages to provide a quotable
    dictionary definition, Andy Pickering proffers a good point of
    departure in his (1995a, p.31):
    
      Cybernetics, then, took computer-controlled gun control and layered
      it in an ontologically indiscriminate fashion across the academic
      disciplinary board-- the world, understood cybernetically, was a
      world of goal-oriented feedback mechanisms with learning.  It is
      interesting that cybernetics even trumped the servomechanisms line
      of feedback thought by turning itself into a universal metaphysics,
      a Theory of Everything, as today's physicists and cosmologists use
      the term-- a cyborg metaphysics, with no respect for traditional
      human and nonhuman boundaries, as an umbrella for the proliferation
      of individual cyborg sciences it claimed to embrace.
    
    So this definition suggests that military science and the computer
    became melded into a Theory of Everything based upon notions of
    automata and feedback.  Nevertheless, there persists a nagging doubt:
    isn't this still more than a little elusive?  The cyborg sciences do
    seem congenitally incapable of avoiding excessive hype.  For instance,
    some promoters of Artificial Intelligence have engaged in wicked
    rhetoric about "meat machines", but indeed, where's the beef?  After
    all, many economists were vaguely aware of cybernetics and systems
    theory by the 1960s, and yet even then, the prevailing attitude was
    that these were 'sciences' that never quite made the grade, failures
    in producing results precisely because of their hubris.  There is
    a kernel of truth in this, but only insofar as it turned out that
    cybernetics never itself attained the status of a fully-fledged
    cyborg science, but instead constituted the philosophical overture
    toa whole phalanx of cyborg sciences.  The more correct definition
    would acknowledge that a cyborg science is a complex set of beliefs,
    of philosophical predispositions, mathematical preferences, pungent
    metaphors, research practices, and (let us not forget) paradigmatic
    things, all of which are then applied promiscuously to some more or
    less discrete pre-existent subject matter or area.
    
    To define cyborg sciences, it may be prudent to move from the concrete
    to the universal.  First and foremost, the cyborg sciences depend
    upon the existence of the computer as a paradigm object for everything
    from metaphors to assistance in research activities to embodiment of
    research products.  Bluntly: if it doesn't make fundamental reference
    to 'the computer' (itself an historical chameleon), then it isn't a
    cyborg science.  The reason that cybernetics was able to foresee so
    much so clearly while producing so little was that it hewed doggedly
    to this tenet.  And yet, there has been no requirement that the
    science necessarily be about the computer per se; rather, whatever the
    subject matter, a cyborg science makes convenient use of the fact that
    the computer itself straddles the divide between the animate and the
    inanimate, the live and the lifelike, the biological and the inert,
    the Natural and the Social, and makes use of this fact in order to
    blur those same boundaries in its target area of expertise.  One can
    always recognize a cyborg science by the glee with which it insinuates
    such world-shattering questions as: Can a machine think?  How is a
    genome like a string of binary digits in a message?  Can lifeforms
    be patented?  How is information like entropy?  Can computer programs
    be subject to biological evolution?  How can physicists clarify the
    apparently political decision of the targeting of nuclear weapons?
    Can there be such a thing as a self-sufficient "information economy"?
    And most disturbingly: What is it about you that makes 'you' really
    you?  Or is your vaunted individuality really an illusion?
    
    This breaching of the ramparts between the Natural and the Social,
    the Human and the Inhuman, may be the most characteristic attribute
    of the cyborg sciences.  Prior to WWII, there were of course a surfeit
    of research programs which attempted to 'reduce' the Social to the
    Natural.  Neoclassical economics was just one among many, which
    also included Social Darwinism, Kohler's psychological field theory,
    Technocracy, eugenics, and a whole host of others.  However, the
    most important fact about all of these early profiles in scientism
    was that they implicitly left the barriers between Nature and Society
    relatively intact: the ontology of Nature was not altered by the
    reductionism, and controversies over each individual theory would
    always come back sooner or later to the question of "how much"
    of Society remained as the surd of Naturalism after the supposed
    unification.  With the advent of the cyborg sciences after WWII,
    something distinctly different begins to happen.  Here and there, a
    cyborg intervention agglomerates a heterogeneous assemblage of humans
    and machines, the living and the dead, the active and the inert,
    meaning and symbol, intention and teleology, and before we know
    it, Nature has taken on board many of the attributes conventionally
    attributed to Society, just as Humanity has simultaneously been
    rendered more machinelike.  Whereas before WWII, the drive for
    unification always assumed the format of a take-no-prisoners
    reductionism, usually with physicists unceremoniously inserting
    their traditions and formalisms wholesale onto some particular sphere
    of social or biological theory, now it was the ontology of Nature
    itself that had grown ambiguous.  It was not just the bogeyman
    of postmodernism which has challenged the previous belief in an
    independent Nature: the question of what counts as Natural is now
    regularly disputed in such areas as artificial life (Levy, 1992;
    Helmreich, 1995), cognitive science (Dennett, 1995) and conservation
    ecology (Cronon, 1995; Soule & Lease, 1995; Takacs, 1996).
    Interdisciplinarity, while hardly yet enjoying the realm of Pareto
    improving exchange, now apparently takes place on a more multilateral
    basis.  For instance, 'genes' now unabashedly engage in strategies
    of investment, divestment and evasion within their lumbering somatic
    shells (Dawkins, 1976); information and thermodynamic entropy are
    added together in one grand law of physical regularity (Zurek, 1990);
    or inert particles in dynamical systems 'at the edge of chaos' are
    deemed to be in fact performing a species of computation.
    
    This leads directly to another signal characteristic of cyborg
    sciences, namely, that as the distinction between the Natural and
    the Social grows more vague, the sharp distinction between 'reality'
    and simulacra also becomes less taken for granted and even harder
    to discern (Baudrillard, 1994).  One could observe this at the very
    inception of the cyborg sciences in the work of John von Neumann.
    At Los Alamos, simulations of hydrodynamics, turbulence and chain
    reactions were one of the very first uses of the computer, because of
    the difficulties of observing most of the complex physical processes
    that went into the making of the atomic bomb.  This experience
    led directly to the idea of Monte Carlo simulations, which came
    to be discussed as having a status on a par with more conventional
    "experiments" (Galison, 1996).  Extending well beyond an older
    conception of mathematical model building, von Neumann believed that
    he was extracting out the logic of systems, be they dynamical systems,
    automata, or "games"; thus manipulation of the simulation eventually
    came to be regarded as essentially equivalent to manipulation of the
    phenomenon (von Neumann, 1966, p.21).  But you didn't have to possess
    von Neumann's genius to know that the computer was changing the very
    essence of science along with its ambitions.  The computer scientist
    R.W. Hamming once admitted:
    
      The Los Alamos experience had a great effect on me.  First, I
      saw clearly that I was at best second rate...  Second, I saw that
      the computing approach to the bomb design was essential...  But
      thinking long and hard on this matter over the years showed me
      that the very nature of science would change as we look more at
      computer simulations and less at the real world experiments that,
      traditionally, are regarded as essential...  Fourth, there was
      a computation of whether or not the test bomb would ignite the
      atmosphere.  Thus the test risked, on the basis of a computation,
      all of life in the known universe. (in Duren, 1988, pp.430-1)
    
    In the era after the fall of the Wall, when the Los Alamos atomic
    weapons test section is comprised primarily of computer simulations
    (Gusterson,1996), his intuition has become the basis of routinized
    scientific inquiry.  As Paul Edwards (1996) has observed, the entire
    Cold War military technological trajectory was based upon simulations,
    from the psychology of the enlisted men turning the keys to the
    patterns of targeting of weapons to their physical explosion
    profile to the radiation cross-sections to anticipated technological
    improvements in weapons to the behavior of the opponents in the
    Kremlin to econometric models of a post-nuclear world.
    
    Once the cyborg sciences emerged sleek and wide-eyed from their
    military incubator, they became, in Herbert Simon's telling phrase,
    "the sciences of the artificial" (1981).  It is difficult to overstate
    the ontological import of this watershed.  "At first no more than
    a faster version of an electro-mechanical calculator, the computer
    became much more: a piece of the instrument, an instrument in its
    own right, and finally (through simulations) a stand-in for nature
    itself...  In a nontrivial sense, the computer began to blur the
    boundaries between the 'self-evident' categories of experiment,
    instrument and theory" (Galison, 1997, pp.44-5).  While the mere fact
    that it can be done at all is fascinating, it is the rare researcher
    who can specify in much detail just "how faithful" is that particular
    fractal simulation of a cloud, or that global climate model, or that
    particular Rogetian simulation of a psychiatrist (Weizenbaum, 1976),
    or that particular simulation of an idealized Chinese speaker in
    John Searle's (1980) 'Chinese Room'.  It seems almost inevitable that
    as a pristine Nature is mediated by multiple superimposed layers of
    human intervention for any number of reasons -- from the increasingly
    multiply processed character of scientific observations to the
    urban culture of academic life-- and as such seemingly grows less
    immediate, the focus of research will eventually turn to simulations
    of phenomena.  The advent of the computer has only hastened and
    facilitated this development.  Indeed, the famous "Turing Test"
    (discussed below in Chapter 2) can be understood as asserting that
    when it comes to questions of mind, a simulation that gains general
    assent is good enough.  In an era of the revival of pragmatism, this
    is the pragmatic maxim with a vengeance.
    
    The fourth hallmark of the cyborg sciences is their heritage of
    distinctive notions of order and disorder rooted in the tradition
    of physical thermodynamics.  While this will be a topic of extended
    consideration in the next chapter, it will suffice for the present
    to observe that questions of the nature of disorder, the meaning of
    randomness, and the directionality of the arrow of time are veritable
    obsessions in the cyborg sciences.  Whether it be the description
    of information using the template of entropy, or the description of
    life as the countermanding of the tendency to entropic degradation,
    or the understanding of the imposition of order as either threatened
    or promoted by noise, or the depiction of chaotic dynamics due
    to the 'butterfly effect', or the path dependence of technological
    development, the cyborg sciences make ample use of the formalisms of
    phenomenological thermodynamics as a reservoir of inspiration.  The
    computer again hastened this development, partly because the question
    of the 'reliability' of calculation in a digital system focused
    practical attention on the dissipation of both heat and signals;
    and partly because the computer made it possible to look in a new way
    for macro level patterns in ensembles of individual realizations of
    dynamic phenomena (usually through simulations).
    
    The fifth hallmark of a cyborg science is that terms such as
    "information", "memory" and "computation" become for the first time
    physical concepts, to be used in explanation in the natural sciences.
    One can regard this as an artifact of the computer metaphor, but in
    historical fact their modern referents are very recent and bound up
    with other developments as well (Aspray, 1985; Hacking 1995).  As
    Hayles (1990a, p.51) explains, in order to forge an alliance between
    entropy and information, Claude Shannon had to divorce information
    from any connotations of meaning or semantics and instead associate
    it with "choice" from a pre-existent menu of symbols.  "Memory"
    then became a holding-pen for accumulated message symbols awaiting
    utilization by the computational processor, which every so often had
    to be flushed clean due to space constraints.  The association of this
    loss of memory with the destruction of 'information' and the increase
    of entropy then became salient, as we shall discover in Chapter 2
    below.  Once this set of metaphors caught on, the older energetics
    tradition could rapidly be displaced by the newer cybernetic
    vocabulary.  As the Artificial Life researcher Tom Ray put it:
    "Organic life is viewed as utilizing energy...to organize matter.
    By analogy, digital life can be viewed as using CPU to organize
    memory" (in Boden, 1996, p.113).  Lest this be prematurely dismissed
    as nothing more than an insubstantial tissue of analogies and just-so
    stories, stop and pause and reflect on perhaps the most pervasive
    influence of the cyborg sciences in modern culture, which is to treat
    "information" as an entity which has ontologically stable properties,
    preserving its integrity under various transformations.
    
    The sixth defining characteristic of the cyborg sciences is that they
    were not invented in a manner conforming to the usual haphazard image
    of the lone scientist being struck with a brilliantly novel idea
    in a serendipitous academic context.  It is an historical fact that
    each of the cyborg sciences trace their inception to the conscious
    intervention of a new breed of science manager, empowered by the
    crisis of WWII and fortified by lavish foundation and military
    sponsorship.  The new cyborg sciences did not simply spontaneously
    arise; they were consciously made.  The usual pattern (described in
    Chapter 4) was that the science manager recruited some scientists
    (frequently physicists or mathematicians) and paired them off with
    collaborators from the life sciences and/or social sciences, supplied
    them with lavish funding along a hierarchical model, and told them to
    provide the outlines of a solution to a problem which was bothering
    their patron.  Cyborg science is Big Science par excellence, the
    product of planned coordination of teams with structured objectives,
    expensive discipline-flouting instrumentation and explicitly retailed
    rationales for the clientele.  This military inspiration extended far
    beyond mere quotidian logistics of research, into the very conceptual
    structures of these sciences.  The military rationale often imposed
    an imperative of "command, control, communications and information"--
    shorthand, C3 I-- upon the questions asked and the solutions proposed.
    Ultimately, the blurred ontology of the cyborg sciences derives from
    the need to subject heterogeneous agglomerations of actors, machines,
    messages and (let it not be forgotten) opponents to a hierarchical
    real-time regime of surveillance and control (Galison, 1994;
    Pickering, 1995a; Edwards, 1996).
    
    The culmination of all these cyborg themes in the military framework
    can easily be observed in the life and work of Norbert Wiener.
    Although he generally regarded himself as an anti-militarist, he was
    drawn into war work in 1941 on the problem of anti-aircraft gunnery
    control.  As he explained it in 1948, "problems of control engineering
    and of communication engineering were inseparable, and...they centered
    not around the techniques of electrical engineering but around the
    more fundamental notion of the message...The message is a discrete
    or continuous sequence of measurable events distributed in time--
    precisely what is called a time series by statisticians" (1961 [1948],
    p.8).  Under the direction of Warren Weaver, Wiener convened a small
    research group to build an antiaircraft motion predictor, treating
    the plane and the pilot as a single entity.  Since the idiosyncrasies
    of each pilot could never be anticipated, prediction was based on the
    ensemble of all possible pilots, in clear analogy with thermodynamics.
    In doing so, one had to take into account possible evasive measures,
    leading to the sorts of considerations which would now be associated
    with strategic predictions, but which Wiener saw as essentially
    similar to servomechanisms, or feedback devices used to control
    engines.  Although his gunnery predictor never proved superior
    to simpler methods already in use, and therefore was never actually
    implemented in combat, Wiener was convinced that the principles he
    had developed had much wider significance and application.  His report
    on the resulting statistical work, The Interpolation and Control of
    Stationary Time Series (1949), is considered the seminal theoretical
    work in communications theory and time series analysis (Shannon
    & Weaver, 1949, p.85fn).  Yet his manifesto for the new science
    of Cybernetics (1961[1948]) had even more far reaching consequences.
    Wiener believed his melange of statistical, biological and
    computational theories could be consolidated under the rubric
    of 'cybernetics', which he coined from the Greek word meaning
    "steersman".  As he later wrote in his biography, "life is a perpetual
    wrestling match with death.  In view of this, I was compelled to
    regard the nervous system in much the same light as a computing
    machine" (1956, p.269).  Hence military conflict and the imperative
    for control were understood as a license to conflate mind and machine,
    Nature and Society.
    
    While many of the historians (Haraway, Pickering, Edwards, et al.)
    I have cited at the beginning of this chapter have made most of
    these same points about the cyborg sciences at one time or another
    in various places in their writings, the one special aspect they
    have missed is that the early cyberneticians did not restrict their
    attentions simply to bombs and brains and computers; from the very
    start, they had their sights trained upon economics as well, and
    frequently said so.  Just as they sought to reorient the physical
    sciences towards a more organicist modality encompassing mind,
    information and organization, they also were generally dissatisfied
    with the state of the neoclassical economic theory which they had
    observed in action, especially in wartime.  Although the disdain was
    rife amongst the cyborg scientists, with John von Neumann serving
    as our star witness in Chapter 3 below, we can presently select one
    more quote from Wiener to suggest the depths of the dissatisfaction:
    
      From the very beginning of my interest in cybernetics, I have been
      well aware that the considerations of control and communications
      which I have found applicable in engineering and in physiology were
      also applicable in sociology and in economics...  [However,] The
      mathematics that the social scientists employ and the mathematical
      physics they use as their model are the mathematics and mathematical
      physics of 1850.  (1964, pp.87, 90)
    
    V. Attack of the Cyborgs
    
    It is always a dicey proposition to assert that one is living in an
    historical epoch when one conceptual system is drawing to a close
    and another rising to take its place; after all, even dish soaps are
    frequently retailed as new and revolutionary.  It may seem even less
    prudent to attempt the sketch of such a scenario when one is located
    in a discipline such as economics, where ignorance of history
    prompts the median denizen to maintain that the wisdom du jour is the
    distilled quintessence of everything that has ever gone before, even
    as they conveniently repress some of their own intellectual gaffes
    committed in their salad days.  Although the purpose of this volume
    is to provide detailed evidence for this scenario of rupture and
    transformation between early neoclassicism and the orthodoxy after
    the incursion of the cyborgs, it would probably be wise to provide
    a brief outline up front of the ways in which the cyborg sciences
    marked an epochal departure from rather more standard neoclassical
    interpretations of the economy.  The bald generalizations proffered
    in this section will be documented throughout the rest of this volume.
    
    As we have noted, economists did not exactly lock up their doors
    and set the guard dogs loose when the cyborgs first came to town.
    That would have gone against the grain of nearly 70 years of qualified
    adherence to a model of man based upon the motion of mass points in
    space; and anyway it would have been rude and ungracious to those
    physical scientists who had done so much to help them out in the
    past.  Economists in America by and large welcomed the physicists
    exiled by war and persecution and unemployment with open arms into
    the discipline in the 1930s and 1940s; these seemed the sorts of
    folks that neoclassicals had wanted to welcome to their neighborhood.
    The first signs of trouble were that, when the cyborgs came to town,
    the ideas they brought with them did not seem to conform to those
    which had represented "science" to previous generations of economists,
    as we shall recount in Chapters 5 and 6.  Sure, they plainly
    understood mechanics and differential equations and formal logic and
    the hypothetico-deductive imperative; but there were some worrisome
    danger signs, like a nagging difference of opinion about the meaning
    of 'dynamics' and 'equilibrium' (Weintraub, 1991), or suspicions
    concerning the vaunting ambitions of 'operations research' and
    'systems analysis' (Fortun & Schweber, 1993), or wariness about
    von Neumann's own ambitions for game theory (Chapter 6 below).
    For reasons the economists found difficult to divine, some of the
    scientists resisted viewing the pinnacle of social order as the
    repetitive silent orbits of celestial mechanics or the balanced
    kinetics of the lever or the hydraulics of laminar fluid flow.
    
    If there was one tenet of that era's particular faith in science, it
    was that logical rigor and the mathematical idiom of expression would
    produce transparent agreement over the meaning and significance of
    various models and their implications.  However, this faith was sorely
    tested when it came to that central concept of 19th century physics
    and of early neoclassical economics, energy.  When the neoclassicals
    thought about energy, it was in the context of a perfectly reversible
    and deterministic world exhibiting a stable and well-defined
    'equilibrium' where there was no free lunch.  The cyborg scientists,
    whilst also having recourse to the terminology of 'equilibria', seemed
    much more interested in worlds where there was real irreversibility
    and dissipation of effort.  They seemed less worried whether lunch
    was paid for, since their thermodynamics informed them that lunch was
    always a loss leader; hence they were more concerned over why lunch
    existed at all, or perhaps more to the point, what functions did lunch
    underwrite which could not have been performed in some other manner?
    For the cyborgs, energy came with a special proviso called 'entropy'
    which could render it effectively inaccessible, even when nominally
    present; many arguments raged in this period how such a macroscopic
    phenomenon could be derived from underlying laws of mechanics which
    were apparently deterministic and reversible.
    
    The premier language which had been appropriated and developed to
    analyze macroscopic phenomena in thermodynamics was the theory of
    probability.  The cyborg scientists were convinced that probability
    theory would come to absorb most of physics in the near future;
    quantum mechanics only served to harden these convictions even
    further.  By contrast, neoclassicals in the 1920s and 1930s had
    been fairly skeptical about any substantive role for probability
    within economic theory.  Since they had grown agnostic about what,
    if anything, went on in the mind when economic choices were made,
    initially the imposition of some sort of probabilistic overlay
    upon utility was avoided as a violation of the unspoken rules of
    behaviorism.  Probability was more frequently linked to statistics,
    and therefore questions of empiricism and measurement; an orthodox
    consensus on the appropriate status and deployal of those tools had
    to await the stabilization of the category "econometrics", something
    which did not happen until after roughly 1950.  Thus once the cyborg
    sciences wanted to recast the question of the very nature of order
    as a state of being which was inherently stochastic, neoclassical
    economists were initially revulsed at the idea of the market as an
    arena of chance, a play of sound and fury which threatened to signify
    nothing (Samuelson, 1986).
    
    These two predispositions set the cyborg sciences on a collision
    course with that pursued by neoclassical economics in the period of
    its American ascendancy, roughly the 1940s through the 1960s.  Insofar
    as neoclassicals believed in Walrasian general equilibrium (and many
    did not), they thought its most admirable aspect was its stories
    of Panglossian optimality and Pareto improvements wrought by market
    equilibria.  Cyborg scientists were not averse to making use of the
    mathematical formalisms of functional extrema, but they were much less
    enamored of endowing these extrema with any overarching significance.
    For instance, cyborg science tended to parse its dynamics in terms
    of basins of attraction; due to its ontological commitment to
    dissipation, it imagined situations where there were a plurality
    of attractors, with the codicil that stochastic considerations could
    tip a system from one to another instantaneously.  In such a world,
    the benefits of dogged optimization were less insistent and of
    lower import, and thus the cyborg sciences were much more interested
    in coming up with portrayals of agents that just 'made do' with
    heuristics and simple feedback rules.  As we have seen, this prompted
    the cyborg sciences to trumpet that the next frontier was the mind
    itself, which was conceived as working on the same principles of
    feedback, heuristics, and provisional learning mechanisms that had
    been pioneered in gun-aiming algorithms and operations research.  This
    could not coexist comfortably with the prior neoclassical framework,
    which had become committed in the interim to a portrayal of activity
    where the market worked 'as if' knowledge were perfect, and took as
    gospel that agents consciously attained pre-existent optima.  The
    cyborg scientists wanted to ask what could in principle be subject to
    computation; the neoclassicals responded that market computation was a
    fait accompli.  To those who complained that this portrait of mind was
    utterly implausible (and they were legion), the neoclassicals tended
    to respond that they needed no commitment to mind whatsoever.  To
    those seeking a new theory of social organization, the neoclassicals
    retorted that all effective organizations were merely disguised
    versions of their notion of an ur-market.  This set them unwittingly
    on a collision course with the cyborg sciences, all busily conflating
    mind and society with the new machine, the computer.
    
    Whereas the neoclassicals desultorily dealt in the rather intangible
    ever-present condition called "knowledge", the cyborg scientists were
    busy defining something else called information.  This new entity was
    grounded in the practical questions of the transmission of signals
    over wires and the decryption of ciphers in wartime; but the
    temptation to extend its purview beyond such technical contexts proved
    irresistible.  Transmission required some redundancy, which was given
    a precise measure with the information concept; it was needed because
    sometimes noise could be confused with signal, and perhaps stranger,
    sometimes noise could boost signal.  For the neoclassicals, on the
    other hand, noise was just waste; and the existence of redundancy was
    simply a symptom of inefficiency, a sign that someone somewhere was
    not optimizing.  The contrast could be summed up in the observation
    that neoclassical economists wanted their order austere and simple
    and their a priori laws temporally invariant; whereas the cyborg
    scientists tended to revel in diversity and complexity and change,
    believing that order could only be defined relative to a background of
    noise and chaos, out of which the order should temporally emerge as a
    process.  In a phrase, the neoclassicals rested smugly satisfied with
    classical mechanics, while the cyborgs were venturing forth to recast
    biology as a template for the machines of tomorrow.
    
    These sharply divergent understandings of what constituted "good
    science" resulted in practice in widely divergent predispositions as
    to where one should seek interdisciplinary collaboration.  What is
    noteworthy is that while both groups essentially agreed that a prior
    training in physics was an indispensable prerequisite for productive
    research, the directions in which they tended to search for their
    inspiration were very nearly orthogonal.  The most significant litmus
    test would come with revealed attitudes towards biology.  Contrary
    to the impression given by Alfred Marshall in his Principles, the
    neoclassical economists were innocent of any familiarity with biology,
    and revealed miniscule inclination to learn any more.  This did
    not prevent them from indulging in a little evolutionary rhetoric
    from time to time, but this never adequately took into account any
    contemporary understandings of evolutionary theory (Hodgson, 1993),
    nor was it ever intended to.  In contrast, from their very inception,
    the cyborg scientists just knew in their prosthetic bones that the
    major action in the 20th century would happen in biology.  Partly
    this prophecy was self-fulfilling, since the science managers
    both conceived and created 'molecular biology', the arena of its
    major triumph.  Nevertheless, they saw that their concerns about
    thermodynamics, probability, feedback and mind all dictated that
    biology would be the field where their novel definitions of order
    would find some purchase.
    
    Another agonistic field of interdisciplinary intervention from the
    1930s onwards was that of logic and metamathematics.  Neoclassical
    economists were initially attracted to formal logic, at least in part
    because they believed that it could explain how to render their
    discipline more rigorous and scientific, but also because it would
    provide convincing justification for their program to ratchet up the
    levels of mathematical discourse in the field.  For instance, this
    was a major consideration in the adaptation of the Bourbakist approach
    to axiomatization at the Cowles Commission after 1950 (Weintraub
    & Mirowski, 1994).  What is noteworthy about this choice was the
    concerted effort to circumvent and avoid the most disturbing aspects
    of metamathematics of the 1930s, many of which revolved around Godel's
    incompleteness results.  In this regard, it was the cyborg scientists,
    and not the neoclassicals, who sought to confront the disturbing
    implications of these mathematical paradoxes, and turn them into
    something positive and useful.  Starting with Alan Turing, the
    theory of computation transformed the relatively isolated and sterile
    tradition of mathematical logic into a general theory of what a
    machine could and could not do in principle.  As described in the next
    chapter, cyborgs reveled in turning logical paradoxes into effective
    algorithms and computational architectures; and subsequently,
    computation itself became a metaphor to be extended to fields outside
    of mathematics proper.  While the neoclassical economists seemed
    to enjoy a warm glow from their existence proofs, cyborg scientists
    needed to get out and calculate.  Subsequent generations of economists
    seemed unable to appreciate the theory of computation as a liberating
    doctrine, as we shall discover in Chapter 7.  Hence the Bourbakist
    strain of neoclassicism ended up in the dead end of the Sonnenschein/
    Mantel/Debreu and no-trade theorems, whereas computational theory gave
    rise to a whole new vibrant field of computer science.
    
    These are just a few of the ways in which cyborg science came into
    conflict with neoclassical economics over the second half of the 20th
    century.  We will encounter many others in the chapters which follow.
    
    VI. The New Automaton Theatre
    
    Steven Millhauser has written a lovely story contained in his
    collection The Knife Thrower called "The New Automaton Theatre", a
    story which in many ways illustrates the story related in this volume.
    He imagines a town where the artful creation of lifelike miniature
    automata has been carried far beyond the original ambitions of
    Vaucanson's Duck or even Deep Blue -- the machine that defeated Gary
    Kasparov.  These automata are not 'just' toys, but have become the
    repositories of meaning for the inhabitants of the town:
    
      So pronounced is our devotion, which some call an obsession, that
      common wisdom distinguishes four separate phases.  In childhood we
      are said to be attracted by the color and movement of these little
      creatures, in adolescence by the intricate clockwork mechanisms that
      give them the illusion of life, in adulthood by the truth and beauty
      of the dramas they enact, and in old age by the timeless perfection
      of an art that lifts us above the cares of mortality and gives
      meaning to our lives...  No one ever outgrows the automaton theatre.
    
    Every so often in the history of the town there would appear a genius
    who excels at the art, capturing shades of human emotion never before
    inscribed in mechanism.  Millhauser relates the story of one Heinrich
    Graum, who rapidly surpasses all others in the construction and
    staging of automata.  Graum erects a Zaubertheatre where works of the
    most exquisite intricacies and uncanny intensity are displayed, which
    rival the masterpieces of the ages.  In his early career Graum glided
    from one triumph to the next; but it was "as if his creatures strained
    at the very limits of the human, without leaving the human altogether;
    and the intensity of his figures seemed to promise some final vision,
    which we awaited with longing, and a little dread".
    
    And then, at age thirty-six and without warning, Graum disbanded his
    Zaubertheatre and closed his workshop, embarking on a decade of total
    silence.  Disappointment over this abrupt mute reproach eventually
    gave way to fascinations with other distractions and other artists
    in the town, although the memory of the old Zaubertheatre sometimes
    haunted apprentices and aesthetes alike.  Life went on, and other
    stars of the Automata Theatre garnished attention and praise.  Then
    after a long hiatus, and again without warning, Graum announced he
    would open a Neues Zaubertheatre in the town.  The townsfolk had no
    clue what to expect from such an equally abrupt reappearance of a
    genius who had for all intents and purposes been relegated to history.
    The first performance of the Neues Zaubertheatre was a scandal,
    or as Millhauser puts it, "a knife flashed in the face of our art".
    Passionate disputes broke out over the seemliness or the legitimacy of
    such a new automaton theatre.
    
      Those who do not share our love of the automaton theatre may find
      our passions difficult to understand; but for us it was as if
      everything had suddenly been thrown into question.  Even we who have
      been won over are disturbed by these performances, which trouble us
      like forbidden pleasures, secret crimes...  In one stroke his Neues
      Zaubertheatre stood history on its head.  The new automatons can
      only be described as clumsy.  By this I mean that the smoothness
      of motion so characteristic of our classic figures has been replaced
      by the jerky abrupt motions of amateur automatons....  They do not
      strike us as human.  Indeed it must be said that the new automatons
      strike us first of all as automatons...  In the classic automaton
      theatre we are asked to share the emotions of human beings, whom in
      reality we know to be miniature automatons.  In the new automaton
      theatre we are asked to share the emotions of the automatons
      themselves...  They live lives that are parallel to ours, but
      are not to be confused with ours.  Their struggles are clockwork
      struggles, their suffering is the suffering of automatons.
    
    Although the townsfolk publicly rushed to denounce the new theatre,
    over time they found themselves growing impatient and distracted with
    the older mimetic art.  Many experience tortured ambivalence as they
    sneak off to view the latest production of the Neues Zaubertheatre.
    What was once an affront imperceptibly became a point of universal
    reference.  The new theatre slowly and inexorably insinuates itself
    into the very consciousness of the town.
    
    It has become a standard practice in modern academic books to provide
    the impatient modern reader with a quick outline of the argument
    of the entire book in the first chapter, providing the analogue of
    fast food for the marketplace of ideas.  Here, Millhauser's story
    can be dragooned for that purpose.  In sum, the story of this book
    is the story of the New Automaton Theatre: the town is the American
    profession of academic economics, the classic automaton theatre
    is neoclassical economic theory, and the Neues Zaubertheatre is the
    introduction of the cyborg sciences into economics.  And Hienrich
    Graum -- well, Graum is John von Neumann.  The only thing missing
    from Millhauser's parable would a proviso where the military would
    have acted to fund and manage the apprenticeships and workshops of
    the masters of automata, and Graum's revival stage-managed at their
    behest.
    
    end
    



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Mon Jun 25 2001 - 20:29:26 PDT